08 June 2025

Beyond Belief: Desire, Myth, and the Modal Grounds of Knowing

1 From Knowing That to Believing In

In most accounts of knowledge, we are taught to distinguish belief from truth, and truth from justification. Knowing, in this model, is believing the right things for the right reasons — belief that p, where p is a proposition, and belief is judged epistemically valid if it corresponds with a fact and is formed through reliable means. This is the familiar territory of “justified true belief,” long considered the cornerstone of epistemology.

But something essential gets left out of this picture. There is another kind of mental orientation toward the world, one that shapes not what we claim to know, but what we hope for, desire, or commit ourselves to. This is the domain of desiderative meaning, and it asks not, Is this true? but What do I want to be true? or What must I act as though is true?

In this way, we can distinguish between:

  • Belief that: a cognitive commitment, projecting propositions aligned with probability or usuality.

  • Belief in: a desiderative commitment, projecting proposals aligned with obligation or inclination.

Both are semiotic processes, and both are central to human meaning-making — but only one is usually counted as “knowing.” In the relational view we’re developing here, this is an untenable divide.

Knowing with Desire

In the framework of Systemic Functional Linguistics (SFL), both knowing and desiring are types of mental process, and both project meaning. But they do so with different modal alignments. Knowing aligns with the domain of truth and likelihood, while desiring aligns with duty and want — two complementary axes of how we construe meaning potential.

Importantly, both kinds of mental process involve projection: we relate one clause to another in a way that constructs a secondary world — not the actual, but the possible, probable, obligatory, or hoped-for. In this sense, both “I know that it will rain” and “I hope that it will rain” are not just reports but acts of semiotic world-making.

So why has the cognitive dimension — knowing that — been treated as epistemology’s only proper concern?

A Lopsided Epistemology

The answer lies partly in the metaphysics of substance: if the world is made of fixed things and true facts, then knowledge must consist in aligning one’s beliefs with these facts. Desires, in contrast, are seen as subjective, internal, emotional — and thus irrelevant to the epistemic enterprise.

But this distinction collapses under relational scrutiny. If meaning arises through participation — if knowing is becoming-with — then there can be no sharp boundary between truth and value, or between cognition and commitment. Our acts of knowing are always already shaped by what we care about, what we fear, what we long for.

Belief-in, then, is not epistemic excess. It is a fundamental mode of participation in meaning.

Toward a Broader Epistemology

This series takes that proposition seriously. Over the coming posts, we will:

  • Explore the modal dimensions of meaning — probability, obligation, inclination — and how they relate to knowledge.

  • Re-examine myth not just as a cognitive schema (explaining the world), but as a desiderative structure (expressing hope, loss, longing).

  • Recast the observer not as neutral recorder, but as participant, moved by desire as well as reason.

  • And consider what it means to know not only about the world, but to know with it — in resonance, in commitment, in hope.

In short, we want to move beyond the epistemology of facts, and toward an epistemology of commitment. Not to abandon truth, but to enrich our account of what it means to be truthful — not only to the world, but to one another.

2 Mental Process Types and Modal Meaning

If our epistemology is to do justice to both belief that and belief in, then we need to take a closer look at how meaning is construed in language. Systemic Functional Linguistics (SFL) offers a powerful starting point through its categorisation of process types — the different ways that language represents experience.

Among these, mental processes are especially relevant to epistemology. They represent inner experience — what we perceive, think, feel, and want. SFL distinguishes four types of mental process:

  1. Cognitive (e.g. know, think, believe that)

  2. Perceptive (e.g. see, hear, notice)

  3. Desiderative (e.g. want, hope, wish)

  4. Emotive (e.g. like, fear, enjoy)

Each of these constructs reality in a different way, and each projects a different kind of clause — a different world.

What we know and think (cognitive processes) is not the same as what we hope or want (desiderative processes), and yet both types of mental process construct relations between subjects and projected meanings. These are not just private mental states, but semiotic acts — ways of making meaning.

Projection and Modality

In SFL, both cognitive and desiderative mental processes project a secondary clause — one that is not asserted directly, but posited as the content of thought or desire.

Compare:

  • I think that it will rain.

  • I hope that it will rain.

The projected clause is structurally similar, but modally distinct. One projects a proposition, evaluated for probability (likelihood), while the other projects a proposal, evaluated for inclination (want) or obligation (ought).

This distinction is crucial. It tells us that knowing and desiring are not only different mental orientations, but different modal relations to the world. When we believe that, we align ourselves with what we think is likely or true. When we believe in, we align ourselves with what we think is desirable, valuable, or necessary — regardless of its likelihood.

Modal Meaning as Epistemic Ground

Modality, in SFL, refers to a speaker’s orientation toward the validity of a clause. There are two broad types:

  • Modalisation: concerned with propositions (statements), and expressed through probability or usuality.

    • e.g. It will probably rain.

    • e.g. She usually arrives late.

  • Modulation: concerned with proposals (commands, offers, suggestions), and expressed through obligation or inclination.

    • e.g. You must go now.

    • e.g. I really want to help.

In mental projection, these modal meanings get embedded in the subject’s interior world — not just what is, but what could be, should be, or must be, according to some inner compass.

And here’s the key: these modal meanings are not marginal. They are central to how we orient to the world, to one another, and to the future.

In privileging only modalisation — belief judged by likelihood — traditional epistemology narrows the field of knowing. It discounts how meaning is brought forth in the desire to act, to change, to hope, to belong. Desiderative mental processes bring modality to life in a different key.

The Semiotic of Desire

To recognise this is to understand belief-in not as epistemic failure or sentimentality, but as a different orientation to meaning. Desiderative mental processes construe a world not of facts, but of commitments — of what matters, of what calls us forth.

This is the neglected ground of much myth, religion, and ritual — not explanatory systems to be assessed for truth or falsity, but semiotic ecosystems of hope and obligation. We misunderstand them when we reduce them to propositions to be believed that they are true. What they do is help people believe in something — and thus to act, endure, transform.

And that, too, is a way of knowing.

3 Modal Worlds, Real and Imagined

Desiderative mental processes — like hope, wish, want, believe in — do not only reveal something about the speaker's interior state. They also project modal worlds: possible, desirable, feared, or idealised versions of the world that orient human action and meaning.

In this post, we explore how such modal worlds are not illusions or fantasies to be measured against a singular ‘reality’ but are themselves real in a different sense: semiotic realities that motivate, stabilise, and transform material life.

The Function of Modal Worlds

All social meaning is grounded in what we might call shared fictions — not because they are false, but because they are as-if realities: worlds that we orient to, negotiate within, and act upon.

  • When someone says I believe in justice, they are not affirming a fact, but invoking a world — a world in which justice can be hoped for, fought for, and recognised.

  • When someone says I hope to see my grandmother in the afterlife, they are not making a scientific prediction, but participating in a modal world whose structure is ethical, affective, and relational.

Modal worlds can be:

  • Possible (It could happen)

  • Desirable (I wish it would happen)

  • Obligatory (It should happen)

  • Feared (It must not happen)

  • Enchanted (It always happens this way in stories)

These worlds are not secondary to ‘reality’; they mediate it. We move through life not only by perceiving what is, but by imagining what could or should be — and committing to it.

The Ontology of the Imagined

Our culture often contrasts ‘real’ with ‘imagined’ as if the latter is a diminished category. But from a relational and semiotic perspective, the imagined is not a retreat from reality, but an organ of orientation. It is part of how we live in time.

  • We imagine futures to decide what to do.

  • We imagine others' feelings to empathise.

  • We imagine different selves to grow and change.

In this sense, imagining is a way of knowing — not just about the external world, but about what matters. Modal worlds are affectively charged, socially scaffolded, and historically inherited. They are not mere inventions of individual minds but shared and maintained by language, art, ritual, and belief.

To believe in something — whether it’s freedom, a better future, or divine grace — is to live as if that world is real enough to act on. And in that action, the modal becomes material.

Myth as Modal World

This is where myth enters not as primitive cosmology but as modal architecture. A myth does not need to be ‘believed’ propositionally to be meaningful. It evokes a world in which values are dramatised, orientations made visible, and life endowed with purpose.

  • A myth tells us not just what happened, but how to live.

  • It encodes not just facts, but desires, obligations, hopes.

To dismiss myth for lacking propositional truth is to miss its modality entirely. A modal world is not a false representation of what is; it is a relational invocation of what could be — a staging ground for ethics, emotion, and imagination.

Knowing Beyond Propositions

Modal knowing, then, is not concerned with likelihood alone, but with orientation — with how we situate ourselves in relation to possibilities. This is a kind of knowing that moves through hope, longing, promise, commitment. And it can be just as structured, just as meaningful, as propositional reasoning.

To believe in is not to deny reality, but to enact a relationship to it — a relationship shaped by values, desires, and the modal fabric of meaning.

4 Myth as Modal Architecture

In the previous post, we introduced the idea of modal worlds — possible, desired, feared, or idealised worlds that are brought forth by the desiderative mode of meaning. Now we turn to myth as a special kind of modal structure — not merely a story, but a way of orienting desire, value, and possibility.

Beyond Fact and Fiction

Myth is often misunderstood in modern discourse as a kind of failed science — an outdated attempt to explain the world before we had better tools. But this view presupposes that the purpose of myth is explanation in the propositional mode. From a relational perspective, this is a category error.

Myth does not aim to explain what is. It aims to enact what matters.

A myth constructs a world that:

  • Shows what is worth striving for or guarding against.

  • Dramatises the tensions between forces like love and power, chaos and order, sacrifice and survival.

  • Positions the subject in relation to these tensions — as a hero, a pilgrim, a mourner, a supplicant.

In this sense, myth is modal architecture: it shapes the imaginative, ethical, and affective contours of the world we inhabit.

The Modal Grammar of Myth

Like any semiotic structure, myth has its own internal logic — not one of evidence and inference, but of orientation and enactment. Myths:

  • Construe a beginning not to mark historical origin, but to set the terms of a world.

  • Propose a telos — an end or aim — that is less about finality and more about value.

  • Populate the world with forces, often personified, that represent modal oppositions: temptation vs duty, fate vs freedom, harmony vs transgression.

The result is not a static worldview but a living matrix in which meaning unfolds over time. Myths are dynamic: they are re-enacted, retold, ritualised — not to recall past events but to rehearse possibilities.

Belief in vs Belief that

When someone says I believe in the resurrection, they are not necessarily claiming a historical fact (belief that), but enacting a modal commitment (belief in). They are living toward a world in which death is not the last word. The difference is crucial:

  • Belief that is cognitive, evidentiary, propositional.

  • Belief in is relational, affective, ethical.

Myths operate primarily in the second register. They generate possibility spaces within which life can be oriented — and reoriented — in light of longing, loss, hope, or joy.

The Participatory Nature of Myth

To engage a myth is not to assess it, but to inhabit it. We do not stand outside it, judging its truth-value like a neutral observer. We enter it — not as dupes, but as participants in its drama.

This participation is not a matter of literal belief but of modal alignment. One lives as if the world disclosed by the myth is meaningful — and thereby brings it forth, not as delusion, but as semiotic reality.

In this way, myth is not a window onto an objective past, but a mirror that reveals what we value, fear, and strive for — and a map for orienting desire in a world of uncertainty.

Myth as a Technology of Desire

Modernity has sought to displace myth with method — to replace story with system. But desire cannot be methodically bracketed. It finds its way back through new myths: of progress, of nation, of romantic love, of personal branding. The question is not whether we live by myths, but which myths we live by, and whether we do so consciously or blindly.

A relational epistemology does not discard myth. It honours its role as a technology of desire — a way of shaping and sharing our orientations toward the possible, the good, the feared, and the sacred.


5 Literalism and the Violence of Interpretation

As we saw in the previous post, myth is not a statement of facts but a semiotic architecture for desire — a living map of possible worlds that orients meaning, value, and action. But what happens when this modal fabric is flattened? When the world of myth is no longer lived as if it were meaningful, but enforced as though it were fact?

This flattening is literalism, and its consequences are profound.


Literalism: A Collapse of Modal Awareness

Literalism is not simply a misunderstanding. It is a collapse of the modal distinctions that allow language — and life — to function relationally. Where myth opens a space of orientation and participation, literalism closes that space, reducing the polyphony of desire to a single voice of dogma.

In linguistic terms, literalism mistakes a proposal for a proposition, and a modal projection for a statement of fact. The mythic belief in becomes a propositional belief that — and this shift entails a profound change in the mode of knowing:

  • The open-endedness of longing becomes a closed system of doctrine.

  • The ethical encounter becomes an epistemic test of allegiance.

  • The drama of transformation becomes a demand for affirmation.


The Violence of Certainty

This reduction is not neutral. It exerts a kind of epistemic violence, because it enforces a single interpretation as the only legitimate access to meaning. It denies the relational nature of understanding and replaces it with compliance. This violence can take many forms:

  • Doctrinal enforcement: Believe that the story is true, or be excluded.

  • Hermeneutic control: Interpret the text this way, or be condemned.

  • Affective policing: Feel this way about the myth, or be accused of irreverence.

Literalism closes the gap between map and terrain — and then punishes those who notice the difference.


The Myth of Objectivity

Literalism is often defended as a form of reverence — fidelity to the truth of the tradition. But paradoxically, it is a modern deformation of myth, shaped by the same epistemic assumptions it claims to resist:

  • It treats myth as information to be transmitted, rather than a world to be inhabited.

  • It treats knowledge as possession, rather than participation.

  • It confuses semantic fidelity (literal meaning) with modal resonance (relational significance).

In doing so, it imports the epistemology of science — clarity, certainty, reproducibility — into domains where ambiguity, multivalence, and transformation are essential.

Literalism, in this sense, is not too ancient but too modern.


Recovering the Relational Space

To move beyond literalism is not to abandon myth. It is to recover its modal power — its ability to orient and re-orient desire, not by force of fact, but by the ethical and imaginative pull of meaning. This requires:

  • Holding myth lightly — not as an object of possession, but as a living practice.

  • Honouring its affective force — its capacity to move, trouble, or transfigure us.

  • Welcoming multiple readings — not as threats, but as invitations to deeper participation.

In this way, we can recover what literalism obscures: that myth does not demand belief, but invites us into a relation — a shared orientation toward what matters most.


6 Desire and the Ethics of Interpretation

Interpretation is never neutral. It is shaped not only by what we know, but by what we want — our desires, fears, longings, and ethical commitments. To interpret myth, then, is not just to assign meaning, but to position oneself in relation to meaning. It is, inescapably, an ethical act.

In this post, we explore the often-overlooked role of desire in interpretation — not only what the text means to us, but what we hope to find, fear to lose, or seek to preserve in the act of interpreting it.


Beyond Hermeneutics of Suspicion

Much modern interpretation, especially in critical theory, has been animated by what Paul Ricoeur called a hermeneutics of suspicion — an orientation that seeks to unmask hidden ideologies, false consciousness, or oppressive structures. While this approach has yielded important insights, it often presumes:

  • That meaning is hidden and must be uncovered.

  • That the interpreter stands outside the text.

  • That desire is delusion or distortion, to be overcome.

But desire is not always a danger to meaning. Sometimes it is what opens the space of meaning in the first place.


Desire as Interpretive Horizon

Desire orients interpretation because it discloses what matters. It shapes not only what we notice in a myth, but how we respond to it:

  • The one who hopes for redemption will read a myth of descent differently from the one who fears judgment.

  • The one who longs for communion will interpret symbols of unity with different affect than the one who fears loss of self.

  • The one who suffers will not read the promise of transformation as a mere metaphor.

Desire does not cloud meaning; it constitutes its relevance. We do not interpret despite our desires — we interpret through them.


Myth and the Ethics of Response

To treat interpretation as ethical is to ask not just “What does this mean?” but also:

  • “What does this ask of me?”

  • “What kind of world does this myth make possible or impossible?”

  • “Who is excluded, harmed, or uplifted by this reading?”

This means recognising that:

  • Some readings are not wrong, but unjust — they marginalise, erase, or oppress.

  • Some readings are not true, but transformative — they enable life to be lived differently.

  • Some readings are not authorised, but responsible — they bear the weight of care.

Interpretation is thus not merely epistemological. It is existential and ethical: it reveals who we are in relation to what we read.


Desire, Responsibility, and Participation

When we understand desire as an ethical horizon of interpretation, we recover the relational nature of knowing. We are no longer observers extracting meaning from myth, but participants co-creating meaning in light of our desires and responsibilities.

This calls for:

  • Humility: Recognising the limits of one’s own reading.

  • Reverence: Honouring the depth and affective weight of myth.

  • Dialogue: Welcoming other desires, other interpretations, other worlds.

And above all, it calls for care — not only in how we interpret, but in how we live what interpretation reveals.

7 Myth as Transformative Orientation

In the end, myth is not simply a story we tell about the world. It is a way of orienting ourselves within the world — shaping how we perceive, how we feel, how we act, and what we become. It is a map, not of geography, but of possibility.

In this concluding post, we bring together the threads of epistemology, modality, and desire to frame myth not as static belief, but as a living orientation toward transformation — both individual and collective.


Myth as Modal Compass

Throughout this series, we have distinguished two modal grounds of myth:

  • Epistemic: Concerned with truth, probability, evidence — “Is this what happened?”

  • Deontic/desiderative: Concerned with values, obligations, hopes — “Is this the world I long for?”

When we treat myth epistemically, it becomes belief — to be confirmed or denied.
When we treat myth desideratively, it becomes orientation — to be lived into or resisted.

This shift reveals that myth is less a description of reality than a proposal for living. It does not merely represent the world; it opens worlds.


Myth and Transformative Knowing

A myth that truly orients us does more than tell us what is — it transforms what can be. It becomes:

  • A way of seeing ourselves and others anew.

  • A source of courage in times of despair.

  • A frame through which action gains coherence and consequence.

Knowing myth, in this sense, is not a matter of having facts, but of being grasped — and moved — by meaning. It is a form of knowing-with: with the body, with the heart, with the community, with the Earth.


Myth and Ethical Becoming

Because myth shapes how we live, it bears an ethical weight. A transformative orientation is not just one that feels meaningful — but one that:

  • Respects difference.

  • Cultivates responsibility.

  • Enables flourishing across boundaries of self and other.

In this light, the question is not “Is this myth literally true?” but:

  • “What kind of person does this myth invite me to become?”

  • “What kind of community does it imagine?”

  • “What world does it make possible?”

Such questions restore myth to its relational role: as a medium of becoming-with — not just knowing-about.


Beyond Belief

If belief says, “I hold this to be true,” and doubt says, “I am not sure,” then orientation says, “I will walk this path.”

This is where myth lives: not in the certainty of facts, nor the insecurity of doubt, but in the courage of participation.

In a fractured world, myths that invite care, transformation, and solidarity are not optional luxuries. They are vital acts of ethical imagination — ways of opening what might yet be.


Closing the Series

This series has suggested that myth is not simply a mode of knowing, but a modality of living. To honour it is not to explain it away, nor to enforce belief, but to recognise how deeply it touches desire, guides becoming, and sustains relation.

In rethinking myth beyond belief, we recover its power as an ethical and existential orientation — one that enables us not just to interpret the world, but to live it otherwise.

Series Reflection: From Knowing About to Living With

This series set out to explore a deceptively simple premise: not all knowing is belief, and not all myths aim to be believed. What began as a distinction between epistemic and desiderative modalities soon unfolded into a deeper inquiry — into the nature of meaning, orientation, and the ethical stakes of what we know and how we live.

What Did the Series Reveal?

  1. Modal Plurality
    The dominant Western tendency to treat knowledge as propositional belief blinds us to the rich diversity of mental processes. Desiderative modes — wanting, hoping, believing in — are not deviations from rational knowing but essential modalities of being-in-the-world.

  2. Myth as More Than Belief
    When viewed solely through an epistemic lens, myth becomes a primitive hypothesis. But when viewed through a desiderative lens, myth becomes a participatory orientation — one that calls us, forms us, and transforms us.

  3. The Observer as Desirer
    We are not just observers of meaning but desiring participants in meaning-making. Our longings shape what we notice, value, and commit to — and thus shape reality as lived.

  4. Myth and World-Making
    Myth is not about returning to a fantasy past but about animating a liveable future. Its truth lies not in its literal accuracy, but in its capacity to call forth new possibilities for ethical co-existence.


How Has This Extended Our Epistemology?

The relational epistemology we’ve been developing is no longer just about knowing-with — it now includes hoping-with, believing-with, and becoming-with. Myth, from this view, is not merely a container of meanings but a relational process that unfolds between participants, desires, values, and time.

Just as belief seeks coherence with reality, hope seeks resonance with possibility. And both are shaped not in isolation, but in co-emergent relation with others — human and more-than-human.

07 June 2025

Epistemology of Scientific Practice and Models

1 The Participatory Nature of Scientific Knowledge

Science is not the discovery of an independent world, but the co-creation of meaning within it.

We often imagine science as a mirror held up to nature — a clean, objective reflection of what is. But what if science is not about uncovering truths out there, but about shaping meaning in relation? What if knowing the world is less like mapping terrain and more like dancing with a partner — where every move we make is part of what the world becomes?

This is the view we want to explore in this series: a relational epistemology of science. Here, knowledge is not possession but participation. It emerges not from distance but from involvement. It is not the capturing of a world but the enacting of one.


From Passive Observer to Active Participant

The classical image of science rests on a powerful dualism: subject and object, observer and observed, knower and known. This split gives rise to the idea that knowledge is a kind of mental copy — a representation that mirrors reality without touching it.

But contemporary insights from quantum physics, systems theory, and the philosophy of science challenge this view. They show that observation is not neutral. Measurement changes what is measured. The very act of inquiry shapes the phenomenon under study. In other words, the observer participates in the construction of knowledge.

This doesn’t mean “anything goes.” Rather, it means that what counts as knowledge always arises within a network of relations — experimental conditions, conceptual models, embodied actions, social norms, and material constraints. There is no view from nowhere. There is only seeing-with, doing-with, knowing-with.


Knowing as Construal

This participatory view aligns with our broader relational ontology. In our previous work, we’ve drawn from systemic functional linguistics (SFL) to distinguish between:

  • Experience — the flux of the world as it unfolds

  • Meaning — how we construe that experience

  • Knowledge — how we make shared construals enduring and accountable

In this light, science is not the passive reception of what is “already there.” It is the construal of experience under particular constraints — constraints that are empirical, conceptual, social, and technological.

A scientific theory is not a mirror but a map. And like any map, it selects, emphasises, and organises according to a purpose. The world it reveals is the world as structured by that purpose.


The Middle Voice of Knowing

To speak of science as participatory is to speak in what some call the middle voice — neither fully active nor fully passive, but co-creative. We do not simply impose form on the world (active), nor simply receive it (passive); rather, we participate in the shaping of what appears.

Science, in this view, is not the extraction of facts from a mute reality. It is a collaborative process of meaning-making. And like any such process, it demands attentiveness, humility, and care.


Looking Ahead

In the posts to come, we’ll unfold this relational view in greater detail. We’ll explore how models act as meaning potentials, how experiments instantiate possibilities, how objectivity becomes a matter of constraint rather than detachment, and how science, at its best, becomes an ethical mode of being-in-relation.

For now, we invite you to sit with this shift:
What if science is not about discovering a world that is, but participating in a world that becomes?


2 Objectivity as Constraint, Not Detachment

In a relational epistemology, objectivity is not about removing ourselves — it's about being accountable to what emerges between us.

The traditional image of science prizes detachment. The ideal observer is a neutral, unaffected presence — rational, disembodied, and nowhere in particular. This conception of objectivity as distance has dominated Western science since the Enlightenment.

But it’s a myth.

No observation is made from outside the world. No measurement is made from nowhere. The scientist is never separate from the system, and the knowledge they produce is never free from framing. Recognising this doesn’t undermine science — it deepens it.

What we need is not less objectivity, but a different kind: one rooted not in detachment but in constraint — a constraint that arises from the interdependence between knower and known.


From Detachment to Dialogue

In our relational view, knowledge emerges within a field of participation. The scientist is not an outsider; they are embedded. The world under study is not passive; it responds.

This doesn’t mean anything can count as knowledge. It means that what counts is shaped through dialogue — a negotiation between experimental intervention, theoretical framing, collective practice, and material resistance.

Here, objectivity is not absence of perspective, but the discipline of making one’s perspective accountable. It is about submitting our construals to shared criteria, repeatable methods, and the test of coherence. It is objectivity within relation, not beyond it.


Constraint as Enabler

What holds scientific knowledge together is not some external Archimedean point, but a system of constraints:

  • Material constraints: what experiments allow and disallow

  • Discursive constraints: what conceptual models make possible or impossible

  • Social constraints: what communities accept as credible or absurd

  • Epistemic constraints: what counts as evidence, falsification, or confirmation

These are not limitations in the pejorative sense. They are enablers of shared meaning. Without them, there is no science — only noise.

Think of a musical scale: it constrains what notes belong, but in doing so it opens space for melody. Scientific objectivity is like this — a productive constraint that makes collective understanding possible.


The Ethics of Objectivity

To pursue objectivity relationally is to take responsibility for how we are entangled with what we study. It’s an ethical stance as much as an epistemic one.

It asks:

  • How are we implicated in this knowledge?

  • What are we leaving out or silencing?

  • Whose interests are being served?

  • What forms of experience are being legitimised or excluded?

These are not threats to science. They are the conditions of its renewal.


Looking Ahead

In the next post, we’ll step back even further to ask how scientific knowledge — and knowledge more broadly — has been shaped by a deeper philosophical shift: from substance to relation. What happens when we stop thinking of the world as made of things, and begin to think of it as made of relations?

Until then, we offer this reflection:
Objectivity is not the erasure of the self. It is the careful, constrained co-becoming of meaning in shared experience.

3 From Substance to Relation

What if the fundamental units of reality are not things, but ways of relating?

In the dominant metaphysical inheritance of Western science, the world is made of substances. These are self-contained, pre-existing entities that possess properties. The role of science, in this view, is to discover those properties and the laws that govern their interactions.

But this substantialist view is not the only option. Nor is it neutral. It reflects a deeper assumption: that things come first, and relations come later — as connections between things.

What if we invert that assumption?


Relation as Foundational

In a relational ontology, relations do not merely link entities — they constitute them. What something is depends on how it is related. The identity of an entity is not prior to relation, but emergent from it.

This shift may sound abstract, but it has profound implications:

  • An electron has no definite position or momentum until it interacts — until a relation is instantiated.

  • A gene is not an independent unit of heredity, but a node in a network of developmental, environmental, and epigenetic processes.

  • A person is not an isolated subject, but a self constituted through social, linguistic, ecological, and historical relations.

These are not exceptions. They are signals that we need a different conceptual frame.


From ‘What is it?’ to ‘How does it relate?’

Substance metaphysics asks what things are. Relation metaphysics asks how they come to be.

This changes the way we understand both ontology and epistemology:

  • Ontologically, the world is not composed of inert building blocks but of fields of co-emergence.

  • Epistemologically, knowledge is not a passive reflection of what is, but a participatory act that helps bring something into being.

Meaning, too, is relational: it arises not from transmission, but from interaction — as we’ll explore further in the next post.


Relational Thinking in Science

Many recent developments in science already point beyond substance:

  • In quantum theory, particles are excitations of a field — and only manifest through interaction.

  • In ecology, no species can be understood apart from its ecosystemic relations.

  • In systems biology, function emerges from networks, not isolated molecules.

  • In linguistics, meaning arises from choices in a system — a set of relational oppositions, not fixed labels.

In all these cases, the unit of analysis is not a thing, but a relation — a pattern, a dynamic, a context.


From Building Blocks to Dynamic Patterns

Relational ontology invites us to stop treating wholes as the sum of parts. Instead, we attend to the patterns of organisation that give rise to both part and whole simultaneously.

This is the ontological ground of our epistemology. If what exists is inherently relational, then knowing is never outside — it is always within the weave.

And this means meaning is not carried, but brought forth. That’s where we’ll turn next.


Preview of Post 4: Meaning Is Not Carried, but Brought Forth
We’ll explore the relational nature of meaning, and why communication cannot be reduced to transmission. If the world is constituted in relation, then so is meaning — and so is knowing.

4 Meaning Is Not Carried, but Brought Forth

What if communication is not transmission, but co-creation?

We often speak as though meaning is something contained in words, ideas, or messages — like freight packed in a box, sent across space to another mind. This is the transmission model of communication, and it underlies much of our thinking in education, media, and even science.

But the relational epistemology we’re unfolding points to a very different model: meaning does not reside in signs; it emerges in their use.


Communication as Enactment

In a relational view, meaning is not pre-given. It is enacted — brought forth in context, through interaction, in real time.

  • A word does not carry a fixed meaning from speaker to listener. It activates a history of meaning potentials within a social and experiential context.

  • A text is not a container of authorial intent. It is a site where meanings are negotiated between readers and the semiotic resources they bring.

  • A scientific model does not mirror reality. It construes a system of relationships that is always partial, always provisional, and always meaningful for someone, in some context.

Meaning, then, is a relational achievement.


Structural Coupling and Participatory Sense-Making

Biologists Maturana and Varela introduced the concept of structural coupling: living systems are not passive receivers of information. They are active participants in their own becoming. They engage with their environment in ways that change them — and change the environment in turn.

From this view, knowing and being are inseparable. We do not merely interpret the world; our interpretations are part of the world’s becoming. We bring forth meaning together — as structurally coupled beings.

This is true not only biologically, but semiotically.


Meaning Is Not Inside Words, Nor Outside Us

Language is not a conduit. It is a relational system. Its power lies not in transferring content but in co-ordinating attention and experience.

  • A metaphor does not explain; it resonates.

  • A scientific explanation does not dictate; it scaffolds understanding.

  • A conversation does not succeed when one speaker’s intention is reproduced in another’s mind, but when something new is made possible between them.

Meaning is not recovered. It is actualised from potential in a particular context, by particular participants, through particular choices.


Implications for Knowing

If meaning is brought forth, not carried, then knowing is not retrieval — it is enactment. And this radically shifts our epistemic stance:

  • We are not neutral observers but active participants.

  • We are not receivers of truth but co-creators of understanding.

  • We are not outside the system, looking in, but always within the field of relations that make knowledge possible.

In other words, we are observers — but as participants. And that is the theme of the next post.


Preview of Post 5: The Observer as Participant
We’ll explore what it means to collapse the false boundary between observer and observed, and why a relational epistemology cannot support the myth of objectivity without position, history, or consequence.

5 The Observer as Participant

Why there is no view from nowhere

Modern science grew in part by insisting on a clear divide between observer and observed — a legacy of Cartesian dualism that sees the knower as outside and above the known. This stance gave us objectivity, repeatability, and precision. But it also came at a cost.

A relational epistemology asks us to re-examine that stance — not to discard rigour, but to rethink what rigour means when we accept that all knowledge is situated, enacted, and co-emergent.


The Observer Enters the Frame

In quantum mechanics, this is not just a philosophical nuance — it’s a physical principle.

  • The act of measurement affects what is measured.

  • The wavefunction collapses not from within itself but through interaction with an observer (or apparatus).

  • The “observer effect” is not a mistake in method, but a feature of reality at its most fundamental level.

To know something, we must engage with it — and in doing so, we alter both it and ourselves.


Participation Is Inescapable

This principle goes far beyond physics:

  • In ecology, the observer shapes the system simply by being present.

  • In linguistics, meaning arises not in utterances alone but in how they are interpreted — by particular listeners in particular contexts.

  • In social science, inquiry affects the community being studied, and vice versa.

  • Even in mathematics, the choice of axioms shapes what can be known.

Every observation takes place from somewhere, by someone, through some means. We are never outside the system. We are always participants in its unfolding.


Positionality and Reflexivity

A relational epistemology embraces positionality: the idea that knowledge is shaped by the position of the knower — culturally, historically, materially, and semiotically.

This does not undermine objectivity; it deepens it. Because it allows for:

  • Reflexivity: knowing that you know from somewhere.

  • Transparency: acknowledging the means and means-of-means through which knowledge is constituted.

  • Accountability: taking responsibility for the ethical and material consequences of what you claim to know.


Science Without Illusions

This is not a call for post-truth relativism. It is a call for science without illusions — science that knows it is a human activity, embedded in relations and powered by interpretation.

Rigour is not the removal of the observer. Rigour is the honest accounting of one's participation.


The Path Ahead

If the observer is always a participant, then knowledge is not something we acquire about the world. It is something we enact with the world.

That’s the focus of the next post:
Post 6: Knowing-with, Not Knowing-about — where we explore what it means to treat knowledge not as possession, but as co-becoming.

6: Knowing-with, Not Knowing-about

Knowledge as co-becoming rather than accumulation

In most traditional accounts, knowledge is imagined as something we have — a substance we accumulate and store. The more we know about the world, the more mastery we gain over it.

But a relational epistemology asks us to reconsider that assumption. What if knowing is not a matter of possession, but of participation? What if knowledge is not a thing, but a process of becoming-with?


From Information to Intra-action

To know about something suggests a separation — a subject here, an object there. But in many domains, especially in quantum physics, this separation does not hold.

  • In Karen Barad’s terms, we do not observe from outside but intra-act from within.

  • Knowing arises not from standing apart, but from engaging in a relationship that brings both knower and known into being.

You do not come to know a forest by mapping it from a satellite. You come to know it by walking among its trees, breathing its air, listening to its rhythms — becoming attuned to its patterns of life.


Situated Knowledge

Feminist epistemologist Donna Haraway called this “situated knowledge.” There is no universal view from nowhere — only partial perspectives from somewhere. But that somewhere is not a limitation; it is a possibility-space. It is how knowledge becomes meaningful.

To know-with is to:

  • Learn through entanglement, not detachment.

  • Let the object of knowledge transform you, not just yield to your analysis.

  • Accept that knowing is a form of mutual becoming — both epistemic and ethical.


In Practice: Knowing-with in Everyday Life

This is not just philosophical. It affects how we relate to:

  • Other people: Do we treat others as data points or as co-authors of meaning?

  • The natural world: Do we extract knowledge from it, or enter into a relationship with it?

  • Language: Do we use it to transmit information, or to bring forth shared understanding?

Knowing-with recognises that meaning is not delivered. It is co-enacted.


Knowledge Is a Verb

The shift from knowing-about to knowing-with is the shift from:

  • Objectivity as distance to objectivity as accountability.

  • Truth as correspondence to truth as resonance.

  • Knowledge as a noun to knowledge as a verb — an unfolding process of becoming-with.

And that brings us to the final post in this series:
Post 7: Knowledge as Ethical Encounter — where we explore the responsibilities that come with knowing in a co-emergent world.

7 Knowledge as Ethical Encounter

Responsibility in a co-emergent world

If knowing is not about standing apart but becoming-with, then every act of knowing is also an ethical act. In a relational epistemology, knowledge is not neutral. It is world-forming — it shapes the realities we inhabit, and the relations we participate in.


What Are We Bringing Into Being?

Every time we engage with the world — observe, interpret, represent — we help bring something forth. We never simply reflect a reality that is already there. We are part of what is actualised.

This raises a profound ethical question:

What kind of world does my knowing help to bring about?

  • Are we enacting a world of extraction, control, and objectification?

  • Or are we enacting a world of reciprocity, care, and mutual recognition?


Knowing Is Never Innocent

This doesn’t mean we must always have perfect knowledge. It means we are responsible for how we participate.

  • In science: Are we treating the Earth as object, or as partner?

  • In media: Are we reporting facts, or reinforcing frames?

  • In education: Are we delivering content, or cultivating capacity for shared meaning?

Knowing involves response-ability — the ability to respond to the other not as object, but as co-constitutive presence.


Towards an Ethics of Entanglement

To know ethically is not to withdraw from complexity. It is to accept that complexity is relational, and that our own position in it matters.

A relational epistemology calls us to:

  • Be accountable for the standpoints we occupy.

  • Be attentive to the ways we shape what we study.

  • Be humble about what can be known without participation.

  • Be open to transformation through the process of knowing itself.


Knowledge as Care

Ultimately, relational knowing is a practice of care — not sentimentality, but sustained attention, receptivity, and respect for the otherness of the other. It is grounded in the recognition that:

To know something truly is to be changed by it.


A New Path of Knowing

With this, the series reaches its conclusion. We have traced a path from objectivist models of knowledge toward a more relational, participatory, and ethical understanding.

  • From knowing-about to knowing-with

  • From observation to entanglement

  • From objectivity as detachment to accountability as care

In a co-emergent world, knowing is not just something we do. It is something we become — together.

06 June 2025

Relational Epistemology: Knowing as Participation

Why Relational Epistemology, and Why Now?

Prelude to a Participatory Turn in Knowledge

We are living through a moment of epistemic reorientation. The cracks in the old edifice are showing. From climate collapse to quantum entanglement, from AI-generated meaning to decolonial scholarship, the question of how we know — and who gets to know — is no longer safely tucked away in the margins of philosophy. It is erupting across disciplines. At stake is not simply a new method, but a new metaphysics: one that rethinks knowledge as a relational act.

This series is an invitation to consider what happens when we stop thinking of knowledge as a substance — as something that can be possessed, transferred, or stored — and start thinking of it as a relation: emergent, situated, participatory.

A relational epistemology begins not with the knower, nor with the known, but with the dynamic between them. It foregrounds encounter over extraction, process over possession. And it does so not as a theoretical luxury, but as a practical necessity in a world where the consequences of our ways of knowing are no longer containable.

Why now? Because the dominant epistemologies of modern science — forged in the image of objectivity, separation, and control — are no longer adequate to the entangled realities they helped reveal. Knowing-as-detachment cannot help us navigate a world constituted by relations. We need a different grammar of knowledge: one that can make sense of intra-action, co-becoming, and the ethical demands of participation.

In what follows, we will sketch the outlines of this relational turn. We will explore what it means to move from substance to relation, from knowing-about to knowing-with, from observer to participant. We will ask what becomes of knowledge when it is treated not as a thing to hold, but as a field of resonance — an unfolding of shared potential between knower and world.

Relational epistemology is not a rejection of science. It is a deeper commitment to its task: to understand the world in ways that remain open to the world’s unfolding. But it is also a reckoning — with the violence of disembodied knowledge, and with the colonial grammars that made conquest appear as comprehension.

What we are proposing here is both radical and ancient. It is a return to the wisdom that knowing is a form of participation. And it is a gesture toward what comes next — an ethics of entanglement, and a science that knows it belongs.

1 What Do We Know When We Know?

“To know is not to grasp a thing, but to participate in a becoming.”

Knowing as a Relational Act

In modern life, we often speak of knowledge as if it were a possession — something you have, something you acquire, something you can hold on to. Knowledge is treated like an object: discrete, transferable, measurable. But this is not the only way to think about knowing.

This series begins from a different premise: that knowing is not possession but participation. To know is not to hold something in the mind, but to enter into relation with it. It is not a static state, but a dynamic becoming-with. Knowledge, in this view, is a process of co-emergence between knower and known.

The Epistemic Myth of Separation

Much of the scientific and philosophical tradition has leaned on an ideal of objectivity — the knower as a detached observer, a neutral spectator peering in on the world from some epistemic nowhere. But this image is itself a fiction. All knowing takes place from somewhere, and every act of knowing implicates the knower.

Relational epistemology begins by acknowledging this: that there is no view from nowhere, and no knowledge without relation. To ask What do we know when we know? is to ask not just about the content of knowledge, but about the relation that gives rise to it.

Knowing as a Mode of Being

To know something is to let it affect you, and to be affected in return. It is not just to register a fact, but to undergo an experience. In this way, knowledge is inseparable from life. It is not a passive reflection of what already is, but a participatory event that helps bring the world into being — and the knower along with it.

This does not mean that anything goes. But it does mean that knowledge is not outside the world. It is one of the ways the world unfolds.

From Representation to Participation

This series sets out to reframe knowledge not as representation but as relation. We will explore:

  • How knowing co-arises with being

  • How objectivity can be redefined as intersubjective coherence

  • How meaning emerges not in things but in relations between things

  • And how this changes our understanding of science, experience, and ourselves

Rather than asking what the world is, we will ask what it becomes in relation to us. This does not reduce reality to subjectivity — but it insists that reality is never independent of relation.

A Shift in Grammar

To help make this shift, we will turn to relational metaphors and models — including ideas from systemic linguistics, quantum theory, and ecology. Where conventional epistemology favours nouns, substances, and categories, relational epistemology foregrounds verbs, processes, and becomings.

Just as we no longer think of an organism as in an environment, but as part of it, we will treat knowledge not as about the world, but as of it — as a mode of participation in its unfolding.

Toward a Relational Epistemology

This is not a denial of truth, but a repositioning of it. Truth is not that which is free from perspective, but that which is coherent within a relation. And as we will see, this view does not make knowledge less rigorous — it makes it more accountable, because it acknowledges the place of the knower in what is known.

In the posts that follow, we will unpack this framework step by step. But we begin here, with the simple question: What do we know when we know?
And with the tentative answer: We know the relation. We know the becoming. We know the participation.

2 There Is No View from Nowhere

“All knowledge is from a place, by a body, through a history. There is no clean window onto the world.”

The Illusion of Detachment

The classical ideal of knowledge assumes a kind of purity: that the knower can withdraw from the world, erase their particularity, and see things as they really are. This is the image of the detached observer — standing outside the world, unmoved and untouched, recording its truths from a privileged distance.

It is a powerful image, and it has served the rise of modern science. But it is not how knowing works.

Every act of knowing is embedded in a context: physical, cultural, linguistic, historical. What we know is shaped by who we are, where we are, and how we have learned to attend. There is no such thing as a neutral gaze.

Situated Knowers

To say that knowledge is situated is not to say it is arbitrary. It is to say it is relational. The world we know is not the world in itself, but the world in relation to us. This does not mean that the world is a projection of the mind — but it does mean that every knower brings something to the relation.

The tools we use to know — our concepts, our categories, our grammars — are themselves the products of our histories. And these shape what we can see, and how we can see it.

The Observer Is Inside the System

This truth becomes particularly evident in quantum mechanics. The observer is not an external party but an active participant in what is observed. Measurement does not merely reveal the state of a system; it contributes to that state.

But this is not just a feature of physics. It is a feature of all knowing. The observer is always inside the system they seek to understand — not perched above it, but entangled in it.

Objectivity Reframed

What, then, becomes of objectivity?

Relational epistemology does not reject objectivity, but redefines it. It is no longer the fantasy of a view from nowhere. It is the practice of accountable positioning — of making visible the standpoint from which knowledge emerges, and the relations that sustain it.

Objectivity becomes less about detachment and more about transparency. It means recognising one’s own embeddedness, and cultivating intersubjective rigour: that is, coherence and consistency across perspectives, rather than erasure of perspective itself.

Knowing-in-Relation

There is no view from nowhere — and that’s not a flaw, it’s a feature. It is what makes knowledge dynamic, plural, and alive. We do not uncover a pre-given world, but participate in the unfolding of one.

This does not collapse truth into relativism. It calls us to a deeper responsibility: to recognise the world not as a fixed object to be mastered, but as a shared becoming to be navigated — together, from where we are.

3 From Substance to Relation

“What if the fundamental units of reality are not things, but relationships?”

The Legacy of Substances

Western thought has long been shaped by a metaphysics of substance. From Aristotle to Descartes to Newton, the world has been imagined as composed of discrete, self-contained entities — things with properties, existing in a neutral backdrop of space and time.

In this view, relations are secondary. A substance can exist on its own; relationships are merely add-ons, accidents of interaction rather than constitutive of being.

But this model begins to break down under closer scrutiny — not only in modern physics, but in biology, cognition, and language. What emerges instead is a vision of reality in which relations are primary.

Fields, Not Particles

Quantum field theory, for instance, tells us that particles are not little marbles flying through space. They are excitations of fields — disturbances in a fabric of relational potential. The identity of a particle is not intrinsic; it is defined by the relational structure of the field in which it appears.

Even mass, energy, and charge are not properties of isolated objects but expressions of relational dynamics. What we call a “particle” is a brief coherence in a larger web — a ripple in the relational sea.

Biology Without Essence

The same shift is echoed in biology. Organisms are not machines made of parts, but processes sustained through ongoing interaction. Life is not a thing, but a pattern of relations — metabolic, ecological, semiotic. A cell only functions in relation to its environment. A species only exists within an ecosystem.

Identity in such systems is not fixed, but fluid — a matter of belonging, co-regulation, and structural coupling.

Language as Relation

Systemic Functional Linguistics (SFL) makes a similar move. It treats language not as a code, but as a social semiotic system: a network of meaning potentials realised in contexts of use. Words do not carry meanings in isolation. They mean in relation to other meanings, and within situations of dialogue.

Meaning is not transferred from speaker to listener like a parcel — it is co-constructed in a field of relation.

Reality as Intra-Action

The physicist-philosopher Karen Barad proposes a powerful term: intra-action. Unlike interaction, which presupposes separate entities that then relate, intra-action suggests that entities emerge through their relations. Boundaries are not pre-given — they are enacted through specific configurations of relational process.

From this view, reality is not made of things that interact, but of relations that materialise as things.

The Relational Turn

To move from substance to relation is not merely to adopt a new vocabulary — it is to reconfigure the ontology on which our epistemology stands. It invites us to see the world not as populated by objects with intrinsic natures, but as a living matrix of interdependencies and co-becomings.

And if what we know is relational, then so too is how we know. Knowledge becomes not an act of extraction, but of attunement — a way of entering into the dynamics of the world as a participant, not an outsider.


4 Meaning Is Not Carried, but Brought Forth

“Meaning is not in the signal, but in the encounter.”

The Container Metaphor

In everyday talk about communication, we often treat meaning as if it were a substance — something contained in words and transferred from one mind to another. This is the conduit metaphor: language as a pipe, messages as parcels, understanding as unpacking.

But this model misrepresents what meaning is and how it arises.

In relational epistemology, meaning is not carried; it is brought forth — enacted, not extracted. What a text, a gesture, or a sound means depends on how it is taken up in a given context, by a given participant, drawing on a history of shared semiotic potential.

Meaning, in other words, does not lie in the form. It emerges with the form in use.

Enacting Meaning: A Second-Order Reality

Systemic Functional Linguistics (SFL) provides a powerful framework for this. Language is a semiotic system, a network of meaning potentials that are actualised through use. The spoken or written text is not a container of meaning — it is an instance, the semiotic actualisation of a specific selection from the meaning potential.

And crucially, the text is not the end of the process. It must be interpreted — that is, instantiated again by a receiver who brings their own meaning potential to the act.

What this means is that meaning is not a first-order property of physical signals. It is a second-order phenomenon — a construal, a co-constructed semiotic reality that emerges in the relation between a meaning potential, a material form, and a participant.

The Participatory Act of Knowing

This relational view resonates deeply with the enactivist tradition in cognitive science. According to Francisco Varela and colleagues, cognition is not the internal representation of a pre-given world, but the bringing forth of a world through embodied action.

Perception is not passive reception, but participation. Meaning arises in the relation between perceiver and world — not in either alone.

Just as a text must be instantiated to mean something, so must a world. Reality as lived is not simply perceived; it is enacted.

Beyond Objectivity

This doesn’t mean “anything goes” or that meaning is purely subjective. On the contrary, meaning is relationally constrained. It is shaped by social systems (like language), by material affordances, and by the histories of meaning-making that precede each act.

What it does mean is that knowledge is not the mirroring of an independent world, but the co-arising of world and knower in the act of knowing.

Objectivity, then, is not neutrality or detachment, but accountability to the relations in which one participates — linguistic, social, ecological, ontological.

From Meaning Transfer to Meaning Participation

To shift from the conduit metaphor to a relational epistemology is to change how we think about understanding itself. It becomes not a transmission, but a transformation — not delivery, but dialogue. Not what does this mean? but how is meaning being brought forth here — and by whom, and for what?

Meaning, in this view, is always in the making.


5 The Observer as Participant

“We never observe from nowhere. We are always already in the world we seek to know.”

The Illusion of Detachment

The classical image of the scientist is that of a detached observer: an individual who stands apart from the system they observe, measuring, recording, and explaining without interfering. This ideal, inherited from Enlightenment rationalism, underpins the notion of objectivity as distance — epistemic cleanliness, untouched by bias or embodiment.

But this image is misleading. Observation is never neutral. It is always situated, always shaped by the means of observation and by the position — conceptual, physical, historical — of the observer. In practice, observation is intervention, and knowledge is not passive discovery but active participation.

From Objectivity to Intra-action

In quantum mechanics, this participatory role of the observer becomes unavoidable. To observe a quantum system is to disturb it — not by accident or technical limitation, but in principle. The system does not possess definite properties until a measurement is made, and that measurement is not a revelation of a pre-existing state, but a co-production of observer and phenomenon.

This is what Karen Barad calls intra-action: not interaction between separate entities, but the entangled co-constitution of meaning, matter, and measurement. The observer is not outside the system; they are a condition of its emergence as a phenomenon.

The Observer in Language

Systemic Functional Linguistics offers a semiotic analogue. Meaning does not pre-exist its expression in language, waiting to be encoded and decoded. Instead, language construes experience — it makes meaning possible by shaping what can be said, thought, and known.

When we interpret language, we do not recover meaning; we re-enact it. The reader or listener is not a passive recipient but a co-instantiator of meaning. What is meant depends on what is said and how it is taken up. In other words, the observer of meaning is a participant in its formation.

Observation as Meaningful Action

In both physics and linguistics, then, we find that observation is not a view from nowhere but a relational act. It involves choice: what to attend to, how to frame it, what to bring forth. These choices are shaped by social, cultural, and historical contingencies — by systems of meaning that both enable and constrain our knowing.

To observe is to act meaningfully — and to take responsibility for how our acts participate in the reality they bring forth.

Participation as Epistemic Responsibility

Relational epistemology does not deny reality, but repositions it. It is not out there, waiting to be mirrored, but arises in and through our relations with it. These relations are not arbitrary, but structured — by language, by embodiment, by history, by matter.

Knowing is not about standing back, but about stepping in — not about removing ourselves from the frame, but about becoming conscious of how we are always already within it.

And with this comes a shift in the meaning of objectivity: from detachment to responsibility for participation.


6 Knowing-with, Not Knowing-about

“To know something is not to hold it at arm’s length but to live with it, respond to it, and become changed by it.”

From Representing to Relating

Traditional epistemology treats knowledge as representation: to know something is to form an accurate mental or linguistic model of it — a picture in the mind that corresponds to a reality outside it. This picture is presumed to be objective, transferable, and detachable from the knower.

But relational epistemology proposes a different metaphor. Knowledge is not a mirror of nature, but a relation with it. It is not a passive likeness of what is, but a process of becoming with. To know is not to depict, but to participate.

Knowing with

This shift from "knowing-about" to "knowing-with" draws attention to the mutuality of knowledge. We do not come to know by standing apart from what we seek to understand, but by entering into dynamic relationship with it — by responding, adapting, co-emerging.

This is evident in ecological science, where knowledge of an ecosystem cannot be abstracted from one's situated involvement with it — the rhythms of the land, the practices of care, the long attention to pattern and change. Indigenous knowledge systems have long recognised this: that to know a river, for instance, is not to measure its flow, but to live with it, fish it, drink from it, speak of it, and listen to it.

Knowing-with is not a metaphorical flourish. It is an ontological orientation.

The Linguistic Analogy

Systemic Functional Linguistics (SFL) provides a powerful lens for this orientation. In SFL, meaning is not encoded and transmitted; it is instantiated — brought forth in context, shaped by the co-deployment of a shared potential. This means that language does not carry meaning from one mind to another. It makes meaning possible by furnishing a terrain on which meaning can be enacted.

To understand a text is not to extract the author's intention, but to enter the same semiotic space and re-live the meaning as one's own — with one's own systems, histories, and interests in play.

Just as meaning is always co-instantiated, knowledge is always co-emergent.

Knowledge as Co-becoming

Relational knowing is not additive — it is transformative. When we know with, we are changed by the encounter. Our understanding grows not by accumulation, but by reconfiguration — of our concepts, categories, identities, and actions.

This kind of knowing cannot be owned. It is not a possession, but a practice — one that takes time, attentiveness, and vulnerability. It is grounded in response-ability: the capacity to be affected and to respond in ways that honour the otherness of what we know with.

Rethinking Objectivity

To know with is to acknowledge that we are never outside the world we seek to know. We are of it, with it, through it. Objectivity, then, is not the erasure of perspective but the deepening of relational accountability — the ethical commitment to let the world matter in how we speak, act, and inquire.


7 Knowledge as Ethical Encounter

“Every act of knowing is also an act of relating — and thus, of responsibility.”

From Epistemology to Ethics

In the classical view, knowledge is ethically neutral: we ask whether it is true, not whether it is good. But relational epistemology insists that the two cannot be separated. When knowing is a form of participation, then every act of knowing is also an act of positioning — a stance we take toward the world and those within it.

To know with something or someone is not simply to grasp or observe, but to enter into relation — to be changed by that relation, and to be accountable to it.

What We Choose to Know

There is an ethics in what we choose to pay attention to, to inquire into, to bring into focus. Do we treat the world as resource — as a stockpile of objects to master and manipulate? Or do we encounter it as presence — as a community of beings to respect and respond to?

In scientific discourse, it is easy to forget that the questions we ask shape the kinds of answers we can receive. The framing of inquiry is already an ethical act — it determines what is rendered visible, and what remains excluded or silenced.

The Matter of Method

Relational epistemology invites us to reframe method itself as an ethical question. How do we approach what we wish to know? Do we isolate, control, and reduce in order to predict and possess? Or do we attend, accompany, and engage in order to understand?

This is not a call to abandon rigour. On the contrary, it is a call to deepen it — to hold ourselves responsible not only for the accuracy of our claims, but for the consequences of our knowledge practices.

Language, Meaning, and Care

As we have seen throughout this series, Systemic Functional Linguistics (SFL) shows that meaning is not passed along but brought forth — co-instantiated in relation. In such a model, understanding is not achieved by decoding, but by enacting: by participating in a shared potential for meaning.

This view reminds us that language is not neutral. It is a semiotic ecology — a living system in which meanings are cultivated, maintained, and transformed. How we mean is always a question of how we live together.

Relational Accountability

To know relationally is to accept that we are not separate from what we know — and that knowledge binds us to the world in new ways. With knowledge comes response-ability — the ethical capacity to respond with care, humility, and attentiveness.

In Indigenous epistemologies, this is not an abstract idea but a lived ethic. Knowledge is relational, and relation implies obligation: to the land, to ancestors, to future generations. Knowing is not a right; it is a responsibility.

The Closing Move

Relational epistemology does not end in certainty. It ends in co-becoming: in the recognition that we know only through our participation in the world, and that this participation is ongoing, unfinished, and open-ended.

In the final account, to know is not to own a truth, but to live in truth — to let the world transform how we see, how we speak, and how we act.