Showing posts with label projection. Show all posts
Showing posts with label projection. Show all posts

08 June 2025

Beyond Belief: Desire, Myth, and the Modal Grounds of Knowing

1 From Knowing That to Believing In

In most accounts of knowledge, we are taught to distinguish belief from truth, and truth from justification. Knowing, in this model, is believing the right things for the right reasons — belief that p, where p is a proposition, and belief is judged epistemically valid if it corresponds with a fact and is formed through reliable means. This is the familiar territory of “justified true belief,” long considered the cornerstone of epistemology.

But something essential gets left out of this picture. There is another kind of mental orientation toward the world, one that shapes not what we claim to know, but what we hope for, desire, or commit ourselves to. This is the domain of desiderative meaning, and it asks not, Is this true? but What do I want to be true? or What must I act as though is true?

In this way, we can distinguish between:

  • Belief that: a cognitive commitment, projecting propositions aligned with probability or usuality.

  • Belief in: a desiderative commitment, projecting proposals aligned with obligation or inclination.

Both are semiotic processes, and both are central to human meaning-making — but only one is usually counted as “knowing.” In the relational view we’re developing here, this is an untenable divide.

Knowing with Desire

In the framework of Systemic Functional Linguistics (SFL), both knowing and desiring are types of mental process, and both project meaning. But they do so with different modal alignments. Knowing aligns with the domain of truth and likelihood, while desiring aligns with duty and want — two complementary axes of how we construe meaning potential.

Importantly, both kinds of mental process involve projection: we relate one clause to another in a way that constructs a secondary world — not the actual, but the possible, probable, obligatory, or hoped-for. In this sense, both “I know that it will rain” and “I hope that it will rain” are not just reports but acts of semiotic world-making.

So why has the cognitive dimension — knowing that — been treated as epistemology’s only proper concern?

A Lopsided Epistemology

The answer lies partly in the metaphysics of substance: if the world is made of fixed things and true facts, then knowledge must consist in aligning one’s beliefs with these facts. Desires, in contrast, are seen as subjective, internal, emotional — and thus irrelevant to the epistemic enterprise.

But this distinction collapses under relational scrutiny. If meaning arises through participation — if knowing is becoming-with — then there can be no sharp boundary between truth and value, or between cognition and commitment. Our acts of knowing are always already shaped by what we care about, what we fear, what we long for.

Belief-in, then, is not epistemic excess. It is a fundamental mode of participation in meaning.

Toward a Broader Epistemology

This series takes that proposition seriously. Over the coming posts, we will:

  • Explore the modal dimensions of meaning — probability, obligation, inclination — and how they relate to knowledge.

  • Re-examine myth not just as a cognitive schema (explaining the world), but as a desiderative structure (expressing hope, loss, longing).

  • Recast the observer not as neutral recorder, but as participant, moved by desire as well as reason.

  • And consider what it means to know not only about the world, but to know with it — in resonance, in commitment, in hope.

In short, we want to move beyond the epistemology of facts, and toward an epistemology of commitment. Not to abandon truth, but to enrich our account of what it means to be truthful — not only to the world, but to one another.

2 Mental Process Types and Modal Meaning

If our epistemology is to do justice to both belief that and belief in, then we need to take a closer look at how meaning is construed in language. Systemic Functional Linguistics (SFL) offers a powerful starting point through its categorisation of process types — the different ways that language represents experience.

Among these, mental processes are especially relevant to epistemology. They represent inner experience — what we perceive, think, feel, and want. SFL distinguishes four types of mental process:

  1. Cognitive (e.g. know, think, believe that)

  2. Perceptive (e.g. see, hear, notice)

  3. Desiderative (e.g. want, hope, wish)

  4. Emotive (e.g. like, fear, enjoy)

Each of these constructs reality in a different way, and each projects a different kind of clause — a different world.

What we know and think (cognitive processes) is not the same as what we hope or want (desiderative processes), and yet both types of mental process construct relations between subjects and projected meanings. These are not just private mental states, but semiotic acts — ways of making meaning.

Projection and Modality

In SFL, both cognitive and desiderative mental processes project a secondary clause — one that is not asserted directly, but posited as the content of thought or desire.

Compare:

  • I think that it will rain.

  • I hope that it will rain.

The projected clause is structurally similar, but modally distinct. One projects a proposition, evaluated for probability (likelihood), while the other projects a proposal, evaluated for inclination (want) or obligation (ought).

This distinction is crucial. It tells us that knowing and desiring are not only different mental orientations, but different modal relations to the world. When we believe that, we align ourselves with what we think is likely or true. When we believe in, we align ourselves with what we think is desirable, valuable, or necessary — regardless of its likelihood.

Modal Meaning as Epistemic Ground

Modality, in SFL, refers to a speaker’s orientation toward the validity of a clause. There are two broad types:

  • Modalisation: concerned with propositions (statements), and expressed through probability or usuality.

    • e.g. It will probably rain.

    • e.g. She usually arrives late.

  • Modulation: concerned with proposals (commands, offers, suggestions), and expressed through obligation or inclination.

    • e.g. You must go now.

    • e.g. I really want to help.

In mental projection, these modal meanings get embedded in the subject’s interior world — not just what is, but what could be, should be, or must be, according to some inner compass.

And here’s the key: these modal meanings are not marginal. They are central to how we orient to the world, to one another, and to the future.

In privileging only modalisation — belief judged by likelihood — traditional epistemology narrows the field of knowing. It discounts how meaning is brought forth in the desire to act, to change, to hope, to belong. Desiderative mental processes bring modality to life in a different key.

The Semiotic of Desire

To recognise this is to understand belief-in not as epistemic failure or sentimentality, but as a different orientation to meaning. Desiderative mental processes construe a world not of facts, but of commitments — of what matters, of what calls us forth.

This is the neglected ground of much myth, religion, and ritual — not explanatory systems to be assessed for truth or falsity, but semiotic ecosystems of hope and obligation. We misunderstand them when we reduce them to propositions to be believed that they are true. What they do is help people believe in something — and thus to act, endure, transform.

And that, too, is a way of knowing.

3 Modal Worlds, Real and Imagined

Desiderative mental processes — like hope, wish, want, believe in — do not only reveal something about the speaker's interior state. They also project modal worlds: possible, desirable, feared, or idealised versions of the world that orient human action and meaning.

In this post, we explore how such modal worlds are not illusions or fantasies to be measured against a singular ‘reality’ but are themselves real in a different sense: semiotic realities that motivate, stabilise, and transform material life.

The Function of Modal Worlds

All social meaning is grounded in what we might call shared fictions — not because they are false, but because they are as-if realities: worlds that we orient to, negotiate within, and act upon.

  • When someone says I believe in justice, they are not affirming a fact, but invoking a world — a world in which justice can be hoped for, fought for, and recognised.

  • When someone says I hope to see my grandmother in the afterlife, they are not making a scientific prediction, but participating in a modal world whose structure is ethical, affective, and relational.

Modal worlds can be:

  • Possible (It could happen)

  • Desirable (I wish it would happen)

  • Obligatory (It should happen)

  • Feared (It must not happen)

  • Enchanted (It always happens this way in stories)

These worlds are not secondary to ‘reality’; they mediate it. We move through life not only by perceiving what is, but by imagining what could or should be — and committing to it.

The Ontology of the Imagined

Our culture often contrasts ‘real’ with ‘imagined’ as if the latter is a diminished category. But from a relational and semiotic perspective, the imagined is not a retreat from reality, but an organ of orientation. It is part of how we live in time.

  • We imagine futures to decide what to do.

  • We imagine others' feelings to empathise.

  • We imagine different selves to grow and change.

In this sense, imagining is a way of knowing — not just about the external world, but about what matters. Modal worlds are affectively charged, socially scaffolded, and historically inherited. They are not mere inventions of individual minds but shared and maintained by language, art, ritual, and belief.

To believe in something — whether it’s freedom, a better future, or divine grace — is to live as if that world is real enough to act on. And in that action, the modal becomes material.

Myth as Modal World

This is where myth enters not as primitive cosmology but as modal architecture. A myth does not need to be ‘believed’ propositionally to be meaningful. It evokes a world in which values are dramatised, orientations made visible, and life endowed with purpose.

  • A myth tells us not just what happened, but how to live.

  • It encodes not just facts, but desires, obligations, hopes.

To dismiss myth for lacking propositional truth is to miss its modality entirely. A modal world is not a false representation of what is; it is a relational invocation of what could be — a staging ground for ethics, emotion, and imagination.

Knowing Beyond Propositions

Modal knowing, then, is not concerned with likelihood alone, but with orientation — with how we situate ourselves in relation to possibilities. This is a kind of knowing that moves through hope, longing, promise, commitment. And it can be just as structured, just as meaningful, as propositional reasoning.

To believe in is not to deny reality, but to enact a relationship to it — a relationship shaped by values, desires, and the modal fabric of meaning.

4 Myth as Modal Architecture

In the previous post, we introduced the idea of modal worlds — possible, desired, feared, or idealised worlds that are brought forth by the desiderative mode of meaning. Now we turn to myth as a special kind of modal structure — not merely a story, but a way of orienting desire, value, and possibility.

Beyond Fact and Fiction

Myth is often misunderstood in modern discourse as a kind of failed science — an outdated attempt to explain the world before we had better tools. But this view presupposes that the purpose of myth is explanation in the propositional mode. From a relational perspective, this is a category error.

Myth does not aim to explain what is. It aims to enact what matters.

A myth constructs a world that:

  • Shows what is worth striving for or guarding against.

  • Dramatises the tensions between forces like love and power, chaos and order, sacrifice and survival.

  • Positions the subject in relation to these tensions — as a hero, a pilgrim, a mourner, a supplicant.

In this sense, myth is modal architecture: it shapes the imaginative, ethical, and affective contours of the world we inhabit.

The Modal Grammar of Myth

Like any semiotic structure, myth has its own internal logic — not one of evidence and inference, but of orientation and enactment. Myths:

  • Construe a beginning not to mark historical origin, but to set the terms of a world.

  • Propose a telos — an end or aim — that is less about finality and more about value.

  • Populate the world with forces, often personified, that represent modal oppositions: temptation vs duty, fate vs freedom, harmony vs transgression.

The result is not a static worldview but a living matrix in which meaning unfolds over time. Myths are dynamic: they are re-enacted, retold, ritualised — not to recall past events but to rehearse possibilities.

Belief in vs Belief that

When someone says I believe in the resurrection, they are not necessarily claiming a historical fact (belief that), but enacting a modal commitment (belief in). They are living toward a world in which death is not the last word. The difference is crucial:

  • Belief that is cognitive, evidentiary, propositional.

  • Belief in is relational, affective, ethical.

Myths operate primarily in the second register. They generate possibility spaces within which life can be oriented — and reoriented — in light of longing, loss, hope, or joy.

The Participatory Nature of Myth

To engage a myth is not to assess it, but to inhabit it. We do not stand outside it, judging its truth-value like a neutral observer. We enter it — not as dupes, but as participants in its drama.

This participation is not a matter of literal belief but of modal alignment. One lives as if the world disclosed by the myth is meaningful — and thereby brings it forth, not as delusion, but as semiotic reality.

In this way, myth is not a window onto an objective past, but a mirror that reveals what we value, fear, and strive for — and a map for orienting desire in a world of uncertainty.

Myth as a Technology of Desire

Modernity has sought to displace myth with method — to replace story with system. But desire cannot be methodically bracketed. It finds its way back through new myths: of progress, of nation, of romantic love, of personal branding. The question is not whether we live by myths, but which myths we live by, and whether we do so consciously or blindly.

A relational epistemology does not discard myth. It honours its role as a technology of desire — a way of shaping and sharing our orientations toward the possible, the good, the feared, and the sacred.


5 Literalism and the Violence of Interpretation

As we saw in the previous post, myth is not a statement of facts but a semiotic architecture for desire — a living map of possible worlds that orients meaning, value, and action. But what happens when this modal fabric is flattened? When the world of myth is no longer lived as if it were meaningful, but enforced as though it were fact?

This flattening is literalism, and its consequences are profound.


Literalism: A Collapse of Modal Awareness

Literalism is not simply a misunderstanding. It is a collapse of the modal distinctions that allow language — and life — to function relationally. Where myth opens a space of orientation and participation, literalism closes that space, reducing the polyphony of desire to a single voice of dogma.

In linguistic terms, literalism mistakes a proposal for a proposition, and a modal projection for a statement of fact. The mythic belief in becomes a propositional belief that — and this shift entails a profound change in the mode of knowing:

  • The open-endedness of longing becomes a closed system of doctrine.

  • The ethical encounter becomes an epistemic test of allegiance.

  • The drama of transformation becomes a demand for affirmation.


The Violence of Certainty

This reduction is not neutral. It exerts a kind of epistemic violence, because it enforces a single interpretation as the only legitimate access to meaning. It denies the relational nature of understanding and replaces it with compliance. This violence can take many forms:

  • Doctrinal enforcement: Believe that the story is true, or be excluded.

  • Hermeneutic control: Interpret the text this way, or be condemned.

  • Affective policing: Feel this way about the myth, or be accused of irreverence.

Literalism closes the gap between map and terrain — and then punishes those who notice the difference.


The Myth of Objectivity

Literalism is often defended as a form of reverence — fidelity to the truth of the tradition. But paradoxically, it is a modern deformation of myth, shaped by the same epistemic assumptions it claims to resist:

  • It treats myth as information to be transmitted, rather than a world to be inhabited.

  • It treats knowledge as possession, rather than participation.

  • It confuses semantic fidelity (literal meaning) with modal resonance (relational significance).

In doing so, it imports the epistemology of science — clarity, certainty, reproducibility — into domains where ambiguity, multivalence, and transformation are essential.

Literalism, in this sense, is not too ancient but too modern.


Recovering the Relational Space

To move beyond literalism is not to abandon myth. It is to recover its modal power — its ability to orient and re-orient desire, not by force of fact, but by the ethical and imaginative pull of meaning. This requires:

  • Holding myth lightly — not as an object of possession, but as a living practice.

  • Honouring its affective force — its capacity to move, trouble, or transfigure us.

  • Welcoming multiple readings — not as threats, but as invitations to deeper participation.

In this way, we can recover what literalism obscures: that myth does not demand belief, but invites us into a relation — a shared orientation toward what matters most.


6 Desire and the Ethics of Interpretation

Interpretation is never neutral. It is shaped not only by what we know, but by what we want — our desires, fears, longings, and ethical commitments. To interpret myth, then, is not just to assign meaning, but to position oneself in relation to meaning. It is, inescapably, an ethical act.

In this post, we explore the often-overlooked role of desire in interpretation — not only what the text means to us, but what we hope to find, fear to lose, or seek to preserve in the act of interpreting it.


Beyond Hermeneutics of Suspicion

Much modern interpretation, especially in critical theory, has been animated by what Paul Ricoeur called a hermeneutics of suspicion — an orientation that seeks to unmask hidden ideologies, false consciousness, or oppressive structures. While this approach has yielded important insights, it often presumes:

  • That meaning is hidden and must be uncovered.

  • That the interpreter stands outside the text.

  • That desire is delusion or distortion, to be overcome.

But desire is not always a danger to meaning. Sometimes it is what opens the space of meaning in the first place.


Desire as Interpretive Horizon

Desire orients interpretation because it discloses what matters. It shapes not only what we notice in a myth, but how we respond to it:

  • The one who hopes for redemption will read a myth of descent differently from the one who fears judgment.

  • The one who longs for communion will interpret symbols of unity with different affect than the one who fears loss of self.

  • The one who suffers will not read the promise of transformation as a mere metaphor.

Desire does not cloud meaning; it constitutes its relevance. We do not interpret despite our desires — we interpret through them.


Myth and the Ethics of Response

To treat interpretation as ethical is to ask not just “What does this mean?” but also:

  • “What does this ask of me?”

  • “What kind of world does this myth make possible or impossible?”

  • “Who is excluded, harmed, or uplifted by this reading?”

This means recognising that:

  • Some readings are not wrong, but unjust — they marginalise, erase, or oppress.

  • Some readings are not true, but transformative — they enable life to be lived differently.

  • Some readings are not authorised, but responsible — they bear the weight of care.

Interpretation is thus not merely epistemological. It is existential and ethical: it reveals who we are in relation to what we read.


Desire, Responsibility, and Participation

When we understand desire as an ethical horizon of interpretation, we recover the relational nature of knowing. We are no longer observers extracting meaning from myth, but participants co-creating meaning in light of our desires and responsibilities.

This calls for:

  • Humility: Recognising the limits of one’s own reading.

  • Reverence: Honouring the depth and affective weight of myth.

  • Dialogue: Welcoming other desires, other interpretations, other worlds.

And above all, it calls for care — not only in how we interpret, but in how we live what interpretation reveals.

7 Myth as Transformative Orientation

In the end, myth is not simply a story we tell about the world. It is a way of orienting ourselves within the world — shaping how we perceive, how we feel, how we act, and what we become. It is a map, not of geography, but of possibility.

In this concluding post, we bring together the threads of epistemology, modality, and desire to frame myth not as static belief, but as a living orientation toward transformation — both individual and collective.


Myth as Modal Compass

Throughout this series, we have distinguished two modal grounds of myth:

  • Epistemic: Concerned with truth, probability, evidence — “Is this what happened?”

  • Deontic/desiderative: Concerned with values, obligations, hopes — “Is this the world I long for?”

When we treat myth epistemically, it becomes belief — to be confirmed or denied.
When we treat myth desideratively, it becomes orientation — to be lived into or resisted.

This shift reveals that myth is less a description of reality than a proposal for living. It does not merely represent the world; it opens worlds.


Myth and Transformative Knowing

A myth that truly orients us does more than tell us what is — it transforms what can be. It becomes:

  • A way of seeing ourselves and others anew.

  • A source of courage in times of despair.

  • A frame through which action gains coherence and consequence.

Knowing myth, in this sense, is not a matter of having facts, but of being grasped — and moved — by meaning. It is a form of knowing-with: with the body, with the heart, with the community, with the Earth.


Myth and Ethical Becoming

Because myth shapes how we live, it bears an ethical weight. A transformative orientation is not just one that feels meaningful — but one that:

  • Respects difference.

  • Cultivates responsibility.

  • Enables flourishing across boundaries of self and other.

In this light, the question is not “Is this myth literally true?” but:

  • “What kind of person does this myth invite me to become?”

  • “What kind of community does it imagine?”

  • “What world does it make possible?”

Such questions restore myth to its relational role: as a medium of becoming-with — not just knowing-about.


Beyond Belief

If belief says, “I hold this to be true,” and doubt says, “I am not sure,” then orientation says, “I will walk this path.”

This is where myth lives: not in the certainty of facts, nor the insecurity of doubt, but in the courage of participation.

In a fractured world, myths that invite care, transformation, and solidarity are not optional luxuries. They are vital acts of ethical imagination — ways of opening what might yet be.


Closing the Series

This series has suggested that myth is not simply a mode of knowing, but a modality of living. To honour it is not to explain it away, nor to enforce belief, but to recognise how deeply it touches desire, guides becoming, and sustains relation.

In rethinking myth beyond belief, we recover its power as an ethical and existential orientation — one that enables us not just to interpret the world, but to live it otherwise.

Series Reflection: From Knowing About to Living With

This series set out to explore a deceptively simple premise: not all knowing is belief, and not all myths aim to be believed. What began as a distinction between epistemic and desiderative modalities soon unfolded into a deeper inquiry — into the nature of meaning, orientation, and the ethical stakes of what we know and how we live.

What Did the Series Reveal?

  1. Modal Plurality
    The dominant Western tendency to treat knowledge as propositional belief blinds us to the rich diversity of mental processes. Desiderative modes — wanting, hoping, believing in — are not deviations from rational knowing but essential modalities of being-in-the-world.

  2. Myth as More Than Belief
    When viewed solely through an epistemic lens, myth becomes a primitive hypothesis. But when viewed through a desiderative lens, myth becomes a participatory orientation — one that calls us, forms us, and transforms us.

  3. The Observer as Desirer
    We are not just observers of meaning but desiring participants in meaning-making. Our longings shape what we notice, value, and commit to — and thus shape reality as lived.

  4. Myth and World-Making
    Myth is not about returning to a fantasy past but about animating a liveable future. Its truth lies not in its literal accuracy, but in its capacity to call forth new possibilities for ethical co-existence.


How Has This Extended Our Epistemology?

The relational epistemology we’ve been developing is no longer just about knowing-with — it now includes hoping-with, believing-with, and becoming-with. Myth, from this view, is not merely a container of meanings but a relational process that unfolds between participants, desires, values, and time.

Just as belief seeks coherence with reality, hope seeks resonance with possibility. And both are shaped not in isolation, but in co-emergent relation with others — human and more-than-human.

30 May 2025

Temporalities of Meaning: Relational Time and Becoming

1 Time as the Unfolding of Process — A Relational Reframing

In the modern scientific worldview, time is often imagined as a uniform container — a linear continuum in which things happen. Physics treats it as a fourth dimension alongside the three of space, something we move through or are moved by. But from a relational and semiotic perspective, time is not a container. It is not an empty backdrop against which processes unfold. Rather, time is the very dimension of unfolding itself — the relational axis of becoming.

This view reframes time as neither objective nor subjective, but as inherently semiotic. That is, it is a meaning dimension, emerging from and with the processes it organises. A process is not located “in” time; it constitutes time — just as a conversation constitutes meaning through the very act of being spoken.

From this perspective, time is not a fixed sequence, but a dynamic arising:

  • It unfolds as processes unfold.

  • It becomes through instantiations of potential.

  • It is felt in and through consciousness, not as a clockwork metronome, but as the lived rhythm of meaning.

Potential and Instance

In a relational ontology, we distinguish between potential and instance. This is not just a distinction between the general and the particular, but between structured affordance and actualised relation. In temporal terms:

  • Potential time is the structure of temporal meaning available to be instantiated.

  • Instance time is the actual unfolding of a process — a stretch of becoming that occupies a place on the cline between potential and instance.

For example, the structure of narrative offers culturally shaped potentials for past, present, and future. But these do not exist independently; they are instantiated in texts, in utterances, and in experiences. Narrative time isn’t “in” the story — it is the unfolding of the story itself.

Time and Consciousness

If time is the dimension of unfolding, then consciousness is a process of temporal actualisation. In our neural model — grounded in Edelman’s Theory of Neuronal Group Selection — consciousness is not a substance but a processual selection of patterns. These selections are both temporal and semiotic. They occur over time, but they also constitute time.

Our experiences of flow, delay, anticipation, memory, and repetition are not distortions of objective time — they are the very fabric of meaning-in-becoming. And meaning systems — from language to ritual, from culture to mythology — are the semiotic scaffolds through which such temporal experiences are shaped, shared, and re-actualised.


Toward a Semiotic Cosmology

In this reframing, we are not placing time “within” the world. Rather, we are locating the world — the world as construed — within time as semiotic unfolding. Time is not an object; it is the temporal dimension of meaning itself. And just as meaning is always relational, always patterned and always instantiated anew, so too is time.

In the posts to follow, we will explore how different meaning systems shape temporal experience, how grammar enacts time through tense and aspect, how subjectivity emerges through temporal orientation, and how social structures and imaginative acts give rise to collective temporalities of memory, anticipation, and transformation.

2 Grammatical Time and the Semiotics of Tense

If time is the dimension of the unfolding of processes, then language is one of the primary ways we organise, construe, and enact that unfolding. Every time we speak or write, we are not merely describing time — we are doing time. Through grammar, we instantiate temporal relations, selectively activating patterns of meaning from our cultural and linguistic meaning potential.

At the heart of this linguistic temporality is tense — a system that locates a process in relation to a speaking event. But tense is not simply a representation of clock time. It is a semiotic resource for positioning experience in relation to the act of meaning itself.

The Grammar of Temporal Relation

In Systemic Functional Linguistics, tense is not a label attached to verbs — it is a system of interpersonal and experiential meaning. It allows speakers to construe events as having happened, happening, or about to happen, always from a particular vantage point.

Tense structures time in three primary ways:

  • It positions processes relative to the “now” of the speech event.

  • It orders sequences of events or states — establishing before, after, or simultaneous relations.

  • It frames meanings of completion, continuation, or anticipation through aspectual choices.

In other words, grammatical time is a relational map of becoming — not a neutral record of when something occurred, but a semiotic act of patterning experience.

Tense as Instantiation of Temporal Potential

Every tense selection — whether present perfect, future progressive, or past simple — is an instantiation of potential temporal meaning. The system of tense offers structured affordances for construing temporality, and speakers activate these selectively and creatively.

In this way, tense is not a representation of time in the physical world. It is a social-semantic technology: a cultural scaffold for making temporal distinctions that matter to us — to our purposes, our stories, and our interactions.

Becoming Through Language

In a relational ontology, meaning is always emerging — always on the move between potential and instance. Tense participates in this motion. It allows us to construe what has become, what is becoming, and what may yet become. And it does this not by referring to external clock-time, but by articulating position within the unfolding of meaning itself.

Grammatical time is thus a form of temporal individuation. Each utterance not only positions events in relation to others — it positions us. It creates a self who remembers, a self who anticipates, a self embedded in a fabric of unfolding meaning.


Beyond Tense: Time as Social Semiotic

Tense is only one resource among many. Languages also use modality, mood, temporal adverbials, and narrative structure to construe time. These are not just linguistic conventions — they are ways of inhabiting time. In the posts to come, we’ll explore how these patterns shape subjective and collective temporalities — and how time, far from being uniform or objective, is always situated, enacted, and shared.

3 Subjective Time — Consciousness and the Rhythm of Meaning

If grammatical time is a semiotic system for construing temporal relations, then subjective time is the lived dimension in which those meanings unfold. It is the inner rhythm of becoming — the pulse of consciousness as it moves, not through a fixed timeline, but through streams of experience.

In a relational ontology, time does not exist independently of processes. It is the dimension of their unfolding. And conscious processes — mental and verbal — are no exception. When we attend, remember, imagine, or speak, we do so in time. But not in a time that simply “passes.” We do so in a time that is enacted.

The Pulse of Mental Processes

From the perspective of cognitive neuroscience, consciousness is not a continuous stream, but a sequence of selections — discrete moments of neuronal integration that form higher-order patterns. Edelman’s Theory of Neuronal Group Selection shows how neural processes are selected and stabilised through experience. These momentary integrations give rise to what we call attention, memory, and awareness — and each has its own temporal signature.

In this light, subjective time is rhythmic. It pulses with the dynamic recurrence of processes:

  • Attention flares and fades.

  • Memories surface and retreat.

  • Thoughts spiral, stutter, or leap.

Rather than ticking forward like a metronome, time in consciousness is modulated by the patterns of meaning we instantiate.

The Temporalities of Projection

In language, we enact these rhythms through projection — one clause projecting another in mental, verbal, or emotive processes:

  • I remember that she left.

  • He says it’s raining.

  • We believe they’ll return.

Each of these projected structures marks a temporal shift: not from present to past, but from immediate to distanced, from shared to internal, from the outer world to the inner theatre of experience. Here, time is not measured — it is layered.

Becoming Through Conscious Process

What, then, does it mean to become, in the semiotic space of consciousness?

To become is to mean — to actualise potential into instance through attention, reflection, desire, or action. Time, in this view, is not a stage on which we act. It is a trajectory of instantiation — a continual flow from potential experience into actualised meaning.

In this unfolding, the self is not a fixed point. It is a dynamic attractor, stabilised momentarily by recurrent patterns of meaning, memory, and intention. Subjective time is thus the rhythm of this self-organising flow — the way in which becoming is felt, enacted, and known.

4 Collective Time — Cultural Rhythms and Temporal Habitus

If subjective time unfolds in the rhythms of consciousness, then collective time arises in the patterned flows of cultural life. We don’t simply inhabit time — we inherit it. We are inducted into it through practices, rituals, technologies, calendars, and clocks. These are not neutral instruments. They are semiotic artefacts that coordinate shared temporal experience — synchronising bodies, meanings, and social orders.

The Social Construction of Time

Time is not experienced the same way across all cultures or historical periods. It is shaped by collective patterns of meaning:

  • Some cultures organise time cyclically, emphasising return and renewal.

  • Others emphasise linearity, with beginnings, progress, and ends.

  • Still others live by event time, where processes dictate the flow, not the clock.

These orientations are not simply mental. They are encoded in language, myth, ritual, and practice. In this sense, time is a habitus — a relational field of dispositions shaped by the historical and social structures we live within.

Calendars, Rituals, and the Temporalisation of Meaning

A calendar is not merely a tool for marking days — it is a symbolic scaffold for collective becoming. It tells us:

  • When to celebrate and mourn.

  • When to plant, harvest, or migrate.

  • When to pause, reflect, or begin again.

Religious rituals, national holidays, academic semesters, fiscal years — all of these instantiate temporal meanings that organise our lives. They do more than coordinate schedules; they shape our very sense of significance. They synchronise meaning potentials across individuals and groups, creating shared attractor spaces for cultural identity and action.

Time as a Semiotic Field

In this view, time is not a backdrop for culture — it is a product of semiosis. The meanings we give to birth and death, success and failure, youth and old age, all unfold within temporal categories that are learned, enacted, and inherited.

Just as grammar gives us resources to construe temporal relations in language, so cultural systems give us symbolic resources to construe time in life. These systems evolve through the same dynamics of selection and instantiation that shape the brain and the self. In this way, collective time is not imposed from above — it is continually being remade from within.

5 Nonlinear Time — Memory, Recurrence, and the Spiral of Becoming

Not all processes move in straight lines. Many of the most significant rhythms of human life — growth, grief, healing, insight — unfold in nonlinear time. These are not sequences of cause and effect, but recursive patterns of becoming. In a relational ontology, time is not merely duration, but difference unfolding — and that difference does not always follow a clock or a calendar.

Memory as Temporal Recursion

Memory is not a passive recording of what has passed. It is an active semiotic process — a re-instantiation of past meaning within a present context. In remembering, we do not retrieve static events; we re-enter attractor spaces of experience. What returns is not the past itself, but its relevance to the now.

This recursive quality of memory makes time spiral rather than linear. Old meanings are revisited, revised, revoiced. We do not simply move forward — we turn, we double back, we reframe. Personal identity emerges not from continuity alone, but from this dynamic interplay of past potential and present actualisation.

Mythic and Archetypal Time

Cultures also encode nonlinear time through myth. Myth does not recount history in chronological order. It dramatises eternal recurrence — the patterns that shape meaning across generations. These stories are not bound to once-upon-a-time. They are always now — available for re-enactment in ritual, imagination, and dream.

Archetypes, likewise, are not fixed templates but deep attractors in the collective semiotic field. They recur not because they are eternal substances, but because they offer resonant patterns for making sense of experience — especially in times of crisis or transformation.

The Spiral of Becoming

In this view, time is not an arrow, nor a circle, but a spiral: a recursive unfolding in which each turn builds on what came before, without ever returning to the same point. Transformation is possible precisely because meaning does not repeat identically. Even when we revisit old terrain, we do so from a new perspective — a different position in the unfolding relation.

This spiral temporality allows us to see human development, cultural history, even cosmic evolution not as straight progressions but as recursive self-organising systems — where the future emerges through the creative return of the past.


6: Thresholds of Time — Crisis, Kairos, and Moments of Transformation

Not all moments are created equal. Some shimmer. Some rupture. Some rearrange the whole structure of our becoming. In this post, we explore thresholds of time — liminal moments that defy linear unfolding and mark the emergence of new meaning potentials.

Kairos: Time as Eventfulness

While chronos measures time in quantity — minutes, hours, years — kairos names a different kind of temporality: qualitative time, the right or ripe moment. In a relational ontology, kairos can be understood as a semiotic condensation — a moment when multiple trajectories intersect and a new attractor crystallises.

These are moments when reality feels charged — when the stakes are high, and the next move matters. They may be born of crisis or creativity, suffering or revelation. What makes them threshold moments is not their objective duration, but their transformative potential.

Crisis and Reconfiguration

Crisis literally means "turning point." It is not just a breakdown, but a bifurcation — a moment in which a system becomes unstable enough to shift into a new pattern. In such moments, the attractor landscape of meaning destabilises. Old semiotic patterns no longer hold; new ones are not yet stabilised.

From a relational perspective, this is not collapse but creative disintegration. It is the opening of new possibility — though that opening may be painful, disorienting, or traumatic. Transformation is not guaranteed. But the potential is there.

Rites of Passage and the Ritualisation of Thresholds

Many cultures have recognised the potency of these thresholds and marked them through ritual. Rites of passage frame transitions — birth, adolescence, marriage, death — as semiotic transformations: not just events in time, but reconfigurations of being. They help hold the uncertainty of the in-between, offering symbolic structure for what cannot be managed by chronology alone.

In modern life, we often lack such ritual containers, and so personal thresholds — illnesses, losses, awakenings — may be lived as private chaos. But even in silence, these moments continue to perform their work: to loosen the grip of old forms and open space for the new.

Time at the Edge

Thresholds are temporal edges. They reveal that time is not merely flow but field — patterned, punctuated, marked by intensities. The event is not a dot on a timeline but a relational convergence — a point where multiple potentialities touch down in experience.

To live relationally is to recognise and honour these edges — not to fear the thresholds, but to walk them with awareness, and with care for the meanings that are trying to emerge.


7 Future-Bearing Time — Anticipation, Intuition, and the Pull of Potential

What if the future is not something “out there” waiting to arrive, but something already active within us — a field of potential that calls us forward? In this final post, we explore how meaning systems not only interpret time but participate in the generation of futures.

The Future as Semiotic Gradient

In a relational-semiotic ontology, the future is not an empty space ahead on a clock. It is a gradient of possibility — structured by the meanings we inherit, the patterns we instantiate, and the trajectories we imagine.

Anticipation is not passive waiting. It is attunement to affordance — the capacity to sense what might become, and to orient meaning-making accordingly. Just as physical systems follow gradients of energy, semiotic systems follow gradients of potential meaning.

This is how the future pulls: not as an external force, but as a relational tension within the attractor landscape of consciousness.

Intuition and the Shape of What Is Coming

Intuition may be one way this tension becomes felt. It is not irrational but pre-rational: the resonance of a not-yet-actualised pattern within our current configuration. Intuition gives form to the vague — an inkling, a hunch, a symbolic dream.

We might say that intuition is the semiotic pressure of the future, registering as embodied sense before it becomes articulated in thought or speech.

From a neuronal perspective, this may be the forward reach of dynamic repertoires. From a linguistic perspective, it is the shaping of future speech by the affordances of past and present meaning. Either way, the future is not separate from the present — it is emergent within it.

Imagination as Temporal Agency

Imagination, in this light, is not a detour from reality but a constitutive act. When we imagine a future, we are not simply picturing it; we are participating in its potential actualisation. We reconfigure attractor landscapes. We shift the probabilities of what will come to pass.

This is why storytelling, art, dreaming, and theorising matter. They are practices of future-making — not in the predictive sense, but in the world-forming sense. Every imagined possibility we take seriously begins to alter the field of what seems possible.

Becoming With the Future

To live with future-bearing time is to be aware that the present is not only a product of the past, but a participant in the future. It is to understand becoming as a process not merely of unfolding but of emergent alignment — tuning ourselves to what wants to happen through us.

In this sense, the future is not fate but field — not fixed endpoint but dynamic invitation.


And so we conclude this journey into the temporalities of meaning. In the unfolding of relation, time is not a container, but a participant — a rhythm, a threshold, a lure.

24 May 2025

Relational Ontology and the Philosophy of Science: Rethinking Reality, Explanation, and Meaning in a Semiotic Universe

1 Science in a Semiotic Universe — Reframing the Real

“What we observe is not nature itself, but nature exposed to our method of questioning.”
— Werner Heisenberg

Introduction: A Shift in the Frame

What is science a science of? For centuries, the answer seemed clear: science is the rational study of a mind-independent reality. From Galileo’s mathematical idealism to Newton’s mechanical cosmos, from Einstein’s geometrised space-time to the probabilistic fields of quantum theory, science has often been viewed as a progressive unveiling of what is "really out there."

But what if this framing misunderstands the nature of what science reveals? What if, instead of picturing science as peeling back layers to uncover a pre-given world, we understand it as a mode of semiotic activity — a meaning-making process that instantiates reality through symbolic patterning?

This post inaugurates a new philosophical journey: to rethink science through the lens of a relational ontology grounded in semiotic potential and actualisation. We ask: what becomes of objectivity, explanation, and reality itself, once we acknowledge that observation does not reveal meaning-neutral facts but constitutes meaning in patterned form?


From Substance to Semiotic Process

In classical ontology, the world is made of things — entities with inherent properties, behaving in accordance with causal laws. On this view, science is the disciplined attempt to describe how those entities behave, and to explain their behaviour in terms of underlying mechanisms.

But in the relational ontology we have been developing, this picture dissolves. Entities do not precede relations — they emerge from them. And relations themselves are not static connections between already-formed parts; they are semiotic patterns of possibility instantiated in context.

Here, the world is not made up of substances with relations, but of relations that co-actualise meaning. Science, then, is not about discovering a fixed underlying reality, but about mapping and modelling the patterned actualisation of potential.


Observation as Semiotic Act

In such a framework, observation is not a passive reception of sensory data. It is a transformative act that selects from the space of potential meanings, instantiating one pathway through many.

This aligns with the quantum insight: that measurement does not simply reveal a pre-existing state but plays a role in actualising the state that becomes real. More broadly, it recognises that all scientific observation is interpretation — not in the sense of subjectivity or bias, but in the stronger sense that meaning is only constituted through systemic patterning.

As Halliday taught us in his systemic-functional model of language, meaning arises not from individual elements, but from their systemic options and their realisation as instances in context. Likewise, in science, a datum is not a raw fact; it is an instantiated semiotic selection from a structured field of potential.


Theory as Patterned Meaning

Scientific theories, in this light, are not metaphysical truths or approximate mirrors of reality. They are symbolic systems — semiotic constructs that make certain kinds of patterned meaning possible.

This does not undermine their power. On the contrary, it shows why they work: because they are resonant attractors in the space of possible meanings, enabling coherent instantiations across contexts and scales. The power of a theory lies not in its "truth correspondence" to the world, but in its ability to pattern potential in ways that are stable, generalisable, and productive.

What is universal, then, is not the content of a theory, but its metafunction: its capacity to model experience, structure discourse, and guide intervention.


Meaning as the Real

This perspective suggests a radical shift: reality itself is not what exists independently of us, but what becomes actual through meaning. This is not to collapse the world into subjectivity, but to recognise that meaning is the dimension through which experience becomes structured, constrained, and shared.

A semiotic universe is not less real — it is more patterned, more complex, more open to emergence and transformation. And science, within this universe, is not the objective mirror of the world, but the semiotic practice of making experience intelligible and tractable through symbolic constraint.


Looking Ahead

If science is a meaning-making activity grounded in a relational semiotic ontology, then many of its foundational assumptions must be reconsidered. What becomes of explanation, when causes are no longer things but constraints? How should we understand laws, when they are not imposed on a passive reality but selected patterns of potential? And what role do we — as observers, theorists, and participants — play in instantiating the world we seek to know?

These are the questions that will guide us in the posts to come.


The Ontology of Explanation — From Causes to Constraints

“Science does not explain the world in terms of things, but in terms of structure and transformation.”
— Gregory Bateson

Introduction: What Is an Explanation?

In the classical view, to explain is to reduce: to show how a phenomenon can be deduced from more fundamental laws, forces, or constituents. Whether in Newtonian mechanics, thermodynamics, or molecular biology, explanation has often meant identifying the efficient cause — that which brings about an effect.

But this causal model of explanation rests on a substance-based ontology. If we reconceive the world not as a collection of self-contained entities but as a relational system of patterned potential, the very idea of cause and explanation must be rethought.

In this post, we explore what it means to explain in a semiotic and relational universe, where constraints — not causes — shape the actualisation of meaning, and where explanation becomes the modelling of pathways through a space of possibility.


From Efficient Cause to Enabling Constraint

Traditional scientific explanation focuses on what caused what. But in a relational ontology, nothing simply causes anything else in a linear chain. Rather, relations constrain — they select, shape, and enable what can happen, given what else is happening.

In this sense, explanation becomes less about identifying a single efficient cause, and more about mapping a space of compatible patterns: what is possible, what is probable, and what is constrained. It is not “A caused B” but “A constrained B to actualise in this way, rather than another.”

Constraints are not passive limitations. They are active patternings of potential — the architecture within which processes unfold. A law of motion, a chemical binding condition, a thermodynamic gradient: each is a constraint that structures what can become actual.


Relational Systems and Explanation as Selection

In a systemic-functional view, to explain a phenomenon is to show how it was selected from a structured system of alternatives. This echoes Halliday’s insight that language is a system of choices — and that what is said is only meaningful in relation to what might have been said but wasn’t.

Likewise in science: the explanation of a trajectory, a structure, or a transformation involves showing how it was selected, constrained, or made probable within a relational system of potential states.

This perspective dissolves the need for a privileged base-level mechanism. There is no final “bottom” layer doing the explaining. Instead, different levels of organisation provide different coherent constraints — and explanation means mapping how those constraints pattern emergence at each scale.


Causation as Path Dependency

Does this mean we must abandon causation altogether? Not at all — but we must reconceive it.

In a relational ontology, causation is not a push from past to future. It is a path-dependent unfolding: an instantiation of meaning constrained by both contextual structure and instantial co-selection. Causes are not things; they are regularities of co-instantiation across time and space.

This aligns with how causation is treated in complex systems and process philosophy: not as the transfer of force from one object to another, but as the emergent coherence of patterned processes.


Explanation as Modelling in the Space of Meaning

What then is the function of scientific explanation? It is to build models — not as mimetic mirrors, but as resonant structures that pattern the possible. A good explanation is one that:

  • Maps the space of potential variation relevant to a phenomenon,

  • Identifies the constraints that shape its actualisation,

  • Reveals the interdependencies that give it systemic coherence.

Such explanation is inherently semiotic. It does not eliminate interpretation — it depends on it. For an explanation to work, it must mean something: it must resonate with other patterns of meaning, and be actionable in the context of further inquiry or application.


Why This Matters

This shift from causes to constraints, from mechanisms to meaning, changes how we think about scientific understanding. It de-emphasises reduction and instead foregrounds:

  • Emergence — how new regularities arise under constraint,

  • Context — how explanation depends on the framing system,

  • Relationality — how phenomena exist only in patterned connection.

It also invites new modes of explanation: not just derivation from laws, but narratives of selection, maps of coherence, and tracings of relational potential.


Looking Ahead

In the next post, we turn to the idea of laws of nature. If explanation is not about reduction to mechanism but mapping systemic constraint, then what becomes of natural law? Are laws the ultimate structure of reality — or are they themselves semiotic attractors, stabilised by historical regularity and human interpretation?

3 Laws, Regularities, and the Myth of the Mechanism

"The laws of nature are not the rails along which the world runs, but the tracks left behind by a world in motion."
— Reframing the metaphor

Introduction: What Are Laws?

Scientific laws have traditionally been understood as the bedrock of explanation — fundamental truths about the way the world works. In the classical view, laws govern reality. They are timeless, universal, and mechanistic: they determine what happens, when, and why.

But what if this view itself reflects a particular ontology — one built on substances, mechanisms, and a detached observer? What if the idea of “law” is not a window into the structure of the world, but a semiotic artefact: a way of stabilising patterns within a relational, interpretive process?

This post explores how a relational ontology challenges traditional notions of natural law, reinterpreting laws as emergent regularities, shaped by constraints, sustained by recurrence, and embedded in human meaning-making.


Laws as Constraints, Not Commands

If we abandon the notion of nature as a mechanism — as a clockwork system pushed by forces — then laws cannot be the gears and levers by which it runs.

Instead, laws are expressions of constraint: they describe how systems tend to behave under certain conditions, within particular configurations of relation. They do not govern phenomena, but characterise the constraints that make certain outcomes more likely than others.

In this view, a “law of motion” is not a universal cause, but a pattern of regularity emergent from the structure of interaction — itself subject to revision, reformulation, or replacement as deeper relational structures are uncovered.


From Universal Law to Contextual Pattern

The more science progresses, the less “law-like” laws appear. Newton’s laws work within a limited domain. Relativistic laws supersede them at high velocities. Quantum processes defy deterministic laws altogether. In biology, chemistry, and ecology, what we call “laws” are often statistical tendencies, context-sensitive constraints, or empirically derived regularities.

This is not a failure of science — it is a clue to a deeper ontology. There are no universal, context-free laws because there are no context-free systems. What appears “law-like” is in fact the emergent coherence of relational patterns, stabilised under specific conditions.


Laws as Semiotic Attractors

A key insight from systemic-functional and relational thinking is that regularities are not imposed from above, but arise from the iterative actualisation of potential under constraint. Just as language evolves through repeated co-selections that shape future probabilities, so too do physical and biological “laws” arise through the accumulation of regular patternings in the space of possibility.

In this sense, laws are not transcendent dictates — they are semiotic attractors: stable formations in the unfolding field of relational potential.

They persist not because they are eternal truths, but because they resonate with the constraints of the system, and recur across instantiations. They are as much products of history as they are descriptors of possibility.


The Role of the Observer

A relational ontology necessarily includes the observer — not as a source of bias, but as an agent of actualisation. Scientific laws are not simply discovered; they are constructed through observation, abstraction, and modelling. They emerge at the intersection of:

  • Material regularities — patterns of interaction in the physical world,

  • Semiotic systems — the meaning-making resources of the observer,

  • Epistemic commitments — what counts as explanation, evidence, or simplicity in a given tradition.

In this light, a law is not a brute fact about the universe. It is a relational stabilisation of meaning, co-constituted by the system and its observer-participant.


Laws as Tools, Not Truths

None of this undermines the value of laws. It repositions them. They are not ontological commands, but epistemological tools — compact, powerful ways of describing what systems tend to do, given their structure.

In this sense, a law is more like a well-worn path than a decree. It tells us how systems have moved before, and how they are likely to move again — but it is always provisional, always interpretive, and always open to transformation as new relational structures become relevant.


Looking Ahead

If scientific laws are neither eternal nor external, but relational and semiotic, then we must ask: what does this mean for the realism of science itself?

Does this lead to a collapse into relativism — or to a new kind of realism, grounded not in mechanism, but in meaning?

4 Science as Meaning-Making — Toward a Relational Realism

“Reality is not merely observed by science; it is constituted through the patterned acts of observing.”

Introduction: Reclaiming Realism

After decentring traditional concepts of force, causation, and law, we now arrive at a deeper philosophical question:

If laws are patterns, not commands — and causation is relational, not mechanical — what becomes of scientific realism?

Does a relational ontology dissolve the objectivity of science into a sea of shifting perspectives? Or can we recover a new kind of realism — one grounded not in substance and certainty, but in pattern and participation, in semiotic stabilisation rather than timeless truth?

This post explores how science as meaning-making offers a relational, systemic, and interpretive realism — one that is no less rigorous, but profoundly more reflexive.


The Crisis of Objectivity

Traditional realism rests on the idea of an objective, mind-independent world — one whose structure science progressively uncovers. But quantum theory, relativity, complex systems, and linguistic philosophy have steadily eroded this ideal:

  • Quantum entanglement implies that what is observed depends on how it is observed.

  • Relativistic simultaneity reveals that spacetime is not absolute but contingent on relational configuration.

  • Complex systems show that global patterns emerge from local interactions, not central laws.

  • Semiotics exposes that observation itself is a kind of interpretation — mediated by symbolic systems.

Rather than viewing these developments as epistemic failures, a relational ontology reframes them as ontological insights: the world is not a static container to be mapped, but a dynamic field of potential that becomes actual through semiotic interaction.


A Semiotic Realism

From this vantage point, scientific realism is not a commitment to independent things, but to the resonance of patterns across systems of observation and interpretation.

A scientific theory is not true because it corresponds to an absolute reality, but because it coheres with observed regularities and constrains further interpretations. The “reality” it describes is relationally constructed — not invented, but emergent from:

  • the constraints of the material order,

  • the potential of our symbolic systems,

  • and the histories of interaction that shape their convergence.

This is not relativism. It is a relational realism:
A realism that acknowledges that what counts as real is co-constituted by the relation between observer and observed — between semiotic potential and systemic pattern.


Explanation as Semiotic Stabilisation

In this model, scientific explanation is not the revealing of an underlying cause but the stabilising of meaning across instances.

A good explanation:

  • Selects relevant features from a system of potential,

  • Patterns them in a way that resonates with prior meaning,

  • And constrains future interpretations through its coherence.

Explanation thus becomes a kind of semiotic modelling — not a peeling-back of appearances to reveal essence, but a patterning of relation that transforms potential into structured understanding.

It is precisely because meaning is not fixed that explanation matters.


From Discovery to Co-Actualisation

If meaning is emergent, then scientific knowledge is not merely discovered — it is co-actualised. This has powerful implications:

  • It affirms the participatory role of science — not as an intruder on nature, but as a partner in its unfolding.

  • It locates rigour not in detachment, but in systematic patterning of meaning within and across contexts.

  • It enables us to reclaim the human in science — not as a contaminant, but as an essential conduit for semiotic realisation.

The world science reveals is not separate from us. It is within the relational field of meaning that includes us — our instruments, our concepts, our questions.


A Universe of Meaning

What emerges is a universe not of static stuff, but of resonant attractors in a field of meaning:

  • A world where pattern is prior to part,

  • Where actualisation is a co-emergent process,

  • And where science is a semiotic dance — unfolding through interaction, interpretation, and the modulation of possibility.

This is the vision a relational realism offers: not less real, but more richly so — alive with structure, context, and history.


Looking Ahead

Having reimagined force, causation, law, and realism itself, we now ask:
What does a relational scientific method look like in practice?

How do models, simulations, and explanations operate in this semiotic universe? And how might this shift affect how we teach, conduct, and communicate science?

5 Modelling the World — Simulation, Representation, and Semiotic Construal

“To model is not to mirror but to construe: to shape the possible into patterns of meaning that guide action, interpretation, and transformation.”

Introduction: Beyond the Mirror

In classical views of science, models were seen as simplified representations — mirrors held up to the world. But in a relational ontology, this metaphor collapses.

Models do not reflect reality; they construe it. They make some meanings possible while excluding others. They do not capture a world already given, but co-constitute a world made real through patterned interaction.

This post explores the function of modelling in a semiotic universe: not as passive depiction, but as active participation in the unfolding of relational potential.


From Representation to Construal

To represent is to re-present something already there.
To construe is to give form to meaning — to actualise one possible configuration of relations among many.

In systemic-functional terms, construal involves the selection and co-patterning of features from a system of potential. A model is thus a semiotic artefact:

  • grounded in theoretical choices,

  • shaped by social purposes,

  • and oriented toward practical effect.

Rather than asking whether a model is true or false, we ask:

  • What does it foreground and what does it exclude?

  • How does it organise meaning, and to what end?

  • What systemic potential does it open up — or foreclose?


Modelling as Semiotic Labour

In this light, scientific modelling becomes a kind of semiotic labour — an effort to stabilise meaning across contexts of use.

Every model:

  • Selects features from a domain of interest,

  • Constrains interpretation by forming regularities,

  • And projects possibility by patterning potential.

This labour is never neutral. Even the most mathematical or computational model is embedded in interpretive choices — in what is measured, what is abstracted, and what is deemed relevant.

Models, like metaphors, are productive fictions: not lies, but creative compressions of possibility.


Simulation as Dynamic Construal

If modelling is construal, then simulation is its dynamic form.

Simulations are not executions of given laws, but navigations through spaces of potential:

  • They unfold scenarios under constrained conditions.

  • They produce possible trajectories, not deterministic outcomes.

  • They allow for the emergence of unexpected patterns — which must then be re-construed to become meaningful.

Simulations, like metaphors, are experiments in intelligibility — exploring the coherence of relations within a constructed system.


The Hermeneutics of Science

All this points to a fundamental shift:
Science is not only empirical but hermeneutic — an interpretive activity engaged in the patterned construal of experience.

  • Experiments do not reveal pre-existing truths, but produce conditions under which certain meanings can emerge.

  • Data are not raw, but already semiotically shaped — by instruments, protocols, and theories.

  • Theories are not mirrors, but meta-models: they pattern the patterns, constrain the constraints.

To model, then, is to participate in the emergence of a world — one meaningfully structured, not mechanically revealed.


Rethinking Explanation and Prediction

This view reconfigures the aims of science:

  • Explanation becomes the modelling of systemic pattern, not causal reduction.

  • Prediction becomes projection within a structured space of potential, not certainty over outcomes.

  • Understanding emerges from the resonance between model and context, not from finality or closure.

Models do not contain truth; they guide attention, shape expectation, and orient response.


Looking Ahead

What does all this mean for science as a human project?

If science is a semiotic practice of construal, shaped by cultural, linguistic, and historical systems, then we must ask:

  • How do disciplines evolve as systems of patterned meaning?

  • How are epistemologies tied to the social functions they serve?

  • What happens when we relocate science within the ecology of meaning-making?

6 Science as Culture — Disciplinary Epistemologies and the Ecology of Meaning

“Science is not apart from culture, but a specialised instance of it — a system of meaning patterned for the construal of particular domains of experience.”

Introduction: The Cultural Situatedness of Science

In traditional philosophy of science, science is often viewed as a uniquely objective enterprise — insulated from cultural values, historical context, or interpretive variation.

But from a relational-semiotic perspective, science is a cultural practice:

  • Embedded in social institutions,

  • Expressed through language and modelling,

  • Guided by normative and epistemological commitments.

In this post, we explore how science functions as a disciplinary culture — one that emerges, evolves, and operates within the broader ecology of meaning.


Disciplinary Epistemologies: Culture in Microcosm

Every scientific discipline construes reality through a distinctive system of meaning — a disciplinary epistemology.

These epistemologies differ in:

  • What they count as evidence,

  • What forms of explanation they prefer (e.g., mechanistic, statistical, narrative, systemic),

  • What metaphors and models structure their thinking,

  • What they assume to be knowable — or worth knowing.

A discipline, in this sense, is a semiotic culture:
a patterned system of selection, co-patterning, and instantiation, attuned to particular domains of experience and particular values of intelligibility.


Science as Meaning-Making Practice

From this view, science is not a method for discovering “facts,” but a practice of meaning-making under rigorous constraint.

It operates:

  • In dialogue with nature, not over and above it,

  • Through the construction and negotiation of models, not the passive accumulation of truths,

  • As a self-reflexive community continually revising its own norms, tools, and aims.

Science, like myth or art or religion, is a way that human cultures construe the world. Its authority lies not in escaping meaning, but in achieving specific forms of patterned meaning with high internal coherence and practical power.


The Ecology of Meaning

No discipline stands alone.

Science exists within a broader ecology of meaning: a dynamic, multi-stratal semiotic system encompassing:

  • Language and discourse,

  • Institutional structures,

  • Technological practices,

  • Philosophical assumptions,

  • Cultural narratives and metaphors.

This ecology shapes:

  • What counts as a legitimate question,

  • What models are deemed intelligible,

  • What counts as “objectivity” or “progress”,

  • And how scientific knowledge is mobilised socially and politically.

Science is thus both culturally formed and culturally formative — a meaning system that both emerges from and reorganises the cultural contexts in which it functions.


Objectivity Revisited: Situated but Disciplined

Does this make science relative? Not in any trivial sense.

Scientific practices discipline meaning through:

  • Replication and formal constraint,

  • Community norms of reasoning and critique,

  • Tools for minimising unexamined bias.

But these practices are themselves historically developed and culturally situated. Their power lies not in transcending context, but in establishing stabilised systems of intelligibility within it.

Science is not value-free, but value-structured — and that structure is what enables both its insight and its limitation.


Implications for a Relational Philosophy of Science

Viewing science as a meaning-making culture implies:

  • Epistemological pluralism: Different sciences, different modes of construal.

  • Reflexivity: Awareness of our models as choices, not revelations.

  • Dialogue across domains: Between sciences, and between science and other cultural forms.

  • Responsibility: For how scientific meanings are embedded in social and ecological systems.

Science becomes not a gateway to “reality” but a mode of semiotic orientation — guiding action, shaping futures, and participating in the collective unfolding of meaning.


Looking Ahead

If science is a form of cultural meaning-making, then what does this say about its metaphysical assumptions?

7 Realism Reimagined — What Does It Mean to Say Something Is Real?

“Reality is not what lies behind meaning, but what emerges through its patterned unfolding.”

Introduction: Beyond NaĂŻve Realism

Philosophers of science have long debated realism — the idea that science uncovers truths about a mind-independent world. But what does “real” mean in a universe where:

  • Meaning is not just representation, but construal?

  • Observation collapses potential into instance?

  • Systems are constituted by their relations, not isolated essences?

In this post, we reimagine realism through a relational and semiotic ontology, where what is real is not what exists “out there” apart from meaning, but what emerges through and within meaningful patterning.


The Traditional Divide: Realism vs Anti-Realism

Historically, realism and anti-realism have framed the philosophical debate:

  • Scientific realism claims that scientific theories describe the world as it is — even when unobservable (e.g. electrons, spacetime curvature).

  • Anti-realism (in its various forms: instrumentalism, constructivism) holds that theories are tools for organising experience, not mirrors of reality.

But both positions share a problematic assumption:
That there is a fixed, knowable world independent of our modes of construal — and that science either accesses it or fails to.


A Relational Shift: From Substance to Pattern

Relational ontology reframes this assumption. In this view:

  • Reality is not a catalogue of independent entities.

  • It is a dynamic configuration of relations, stabilised through systems of interaction.

  • What something is depends on how it relates — to other things, to the field in which it’s embedded, to the processes through which it is observed or brought forth.

Thus, to say that something is real is to say:

  • It makes a difference to patterns of experience,

  • It coheres within systems of meaning and practice,

  • It is stable enough across contexts to support inference, action, and further construal.


Meaning as the Medium of Reality

From a systemic-functional perspective, meaning does not obscure reality — it constitutes it.

  • Scientific observation is not passive registration, but active construal.

  • Theories do not describe entities “out there,” but pattern fields of potential, enabling the actualisation of new phenomena.

  • Measurement is not mere detection, but a coupling of observer and system that reshapes both.

Reality, in this view, is not pre-semiotic. It is inherently semiotic — not because the world is made of language, but because our access to the world is always mediated by systems of patterned meaning.


What Kind of Realism Follows?

A relational philosophy supports a form of process-relational realism or semiotic realism:

  • Real are those patterns and potentials that persist, differentiate, and constrain experience through time.

  • Truth is not correspondence to a pre-given world, but coherence and generative power within a semiotic system.

  • Observation does not strip away subjectivity, but entrains patterns of coupling between observer and observed.

Such a realism acknowledges:

  • That science construes — it does not uncover naked facts.

  • That our construals matter — they structure action, perception, and world-making.

  • That stability, not absoluteness, is the mark of realness in a relational world.


Implications: Reality as a Semiotic Field

From this vantage point:

  • Reality is not the thing that escapes meaning.

  • Reality is the space of possibility shaped by systems of meaning — material, biological, social, scientific.

This leads to a vision of the universe as:

  • Relationally textured — no entity apart from interaction,

  • Semiotically emergent — no pattern apart from meaning,

  • Open-ended — new configurations always possible through reorganisation of systems.


8 Reframing Realism — Knowing, Meaning, and the Relational Universe

In the landscape of philosophy of science, few debates are as enduring — or as contentious — as the debate over realism. Are scientific theories describing a world “out there,” independent of our minds and practices? Or are they best understood as useful fictions, instruments for organising experience and predicting outcomes?

Our relational-semiotic ontology reframes this debate — not by denying the challenges to traditional realism, but by transforming the very terms in which they arise.


Realism Revisited: The Traditional Fault Lines

Philosophical realism, broadly construed, claims that science aims to discover objective truths about an independent reality. But this position has long been shaken by formidable critiques:

  • The Pessimistic Meta-Induction: If most past scientific theories (e.g. phlogiston, ether) have proven false, why assume current theories are true?

  • Theory-Ladenness of Observation: What we observe is always shaped by the concepts and expectations we bring — suggesting there is no pure, neutral observation.

  • Underdetermination: Multiple, empirically equivalent theories may fit the same data — so the data alone cannot determine what’s “real.”

  • Constructivist Challenges: Science is a social activity, shaped by values, power, institutions, and culture — calling into question its objectivity.

Such critiques have led some to abandon realism altogether, embracing various forms of instrumentalism, constructivism, or anti-realism. But our relational ontology offers a different path.


From Ontological Independence to Relational Actuality

Our approach does not begin with the premise of an observer-independent world that science progressively uncovers. Instead, it begins with relations — patterns of interaction, unfolding, and constraint — and with semiosis as the process by which such patterns are construed and re-construed.

In this view:

  • Reality is not “out there” as brute existence, but is the semiotic actualisation of potential through relational process. What becomes real is not detached from knowing, but emergent within patterned meaning-making.

  • Science is not about discovering timeless entities, but about construing regularities in the behaviour of systems, across many levels of organisation — from matter and motion to culture and cognition.

  • The “real” is not what escapes interpretation, but what persists through interpretation — what constrains, what patterns, what resists certain construals and enables others.


Reframing the Critiques

Seen from this perspective, the classic anti-realist arguments do not defeat realism — they clarify the kind of realism we must adopt:

  • The Pessimistic Meta-Induction becomes a lesson in evolving construals. Past theories are not false but partial — patterns seen through earlier lenses. Their limits do not invalidate science but point to its recursive deepening of meaning.

  • Theory-ladenness is no longer a flaw to overcome, but a recognition of how all experience is mediated by systems of meaning. Meaning is not an obstacle to truth, but its condition.

  • Underdetermination reminds us that explanation is never simply entailed by data — it is a symbolic act of integration. Competing theories reflect alternate mappings of potential; science advances by tracking which mappings better resonate with constraint.

  • Constructivism rightly highlights science’s social and cultural embeddedness. But this does not undermine science’s claim to truth — it reveals truth as a relational achievement, not an isolated correspondence.


Semiotic Realism: A New Foundation

The realism we defend is not naive correspondence theory. It is a semiotic realism grounded in three key principles:

  1. Relational Actuality: What is real is not static being, but patterned becoming — relational processes that actualise potential.

  2. Meaning as Mode of Reality: Meaning is not a layer added onto the world; it is the way the world comes into being for a knower. Semiosis is ontologically constitutive.

  3. Constraint as Touchstone: The reality of a theory lies not in its finality, but in its fidelity to constraint — its capacity to organise and anticipate how systems behave.

Science, on this view, does not move toward an asymptotic “truth” independent of observers. It moves deeper into the structured space of what is possible under constraint — a movement not of accumulation but of unfolding resonance.


Looking Ahead: From Realism to Meaningful Science

With this post, our reframing of realism culminates in a profound shift: from the search for mind-independent facts to the mapping of meaning-bearing regularities in a semiotic universe. The world science studies is not mute matter, but meaningful materiality — unfolding through our questions, models, and measurements.

In the final post of the series, we will explore what this reframing implies for the future of science itself: How might a science grounded in semiotic realism, relational ontology, and systemic patterning look different from the paradigms we have inherited? What kind of explanation, what kind of inquiry, might emerge from such a vision?


9 Toward a Science of Meaningful Patterns — Futures in a Relational Universe

As we bring this series to a close, we arrive not at an endpoint but at a threshold: a new vantage on what science is, and what it might become. We've reframed causation, law, explanation, and realism within a relational and semiotic ontology. Now we ask:

What kind of science emerges from this worldview? What would it mean to pursue a science not of brute entities, but of meaningful pattern — not of discovering a pre-given world, but of co-actualising its potential through constraint and relation?


From Mechanism to Meaningful Pattern

Traditional science has sought to explain the world in terms of mechanism — discrete parts interacting according to fixed laws. But our relational ontology dissolves this foundation:

  • Entities are not givens but outcomes — stabilised patterns of relation that emerge from ongoing processes of constraint and unfolding.

  • Laws are not prescriptive regularities, but high-level summaries of system dynamics — tendencies that hold within constrained contexts.

  • Causation is not push-and-pull across space, but the modulation of potential across a field of interaction.

What science studies, then, is not the behaviour of isolated things, but the patterning of becoming. A new science would make meaning itself — in its material and symbolic dimensions — the central object of inquiry.


The Tasks of a Relational Science

A science grounded in this ontology does not discard the achievements of existing paradigms — it deepens and recontextualises them. Its tasks might include:

  1. Mapping Fields of Potential
    Systems — from atoms to minds — are not fixed objects but relational configurations of possibility. Science becomes the study of how potentials are constrained, co-activated, or transformed by interaction.

  2. Tracing Emergent Pattern
    Across domains (physical, biological, cognitive, cultural), new forms arise through recursive interactions. A relational science focuses on how pattern emerges, stabilises, diversifies — and how meaning is modulated across scales.

  3. Making Constraint Visible
    Constraint is not limitation but generativity — the structuring of what can unfold. Scientific inquiry becomes a practice of articulating the layered constraints that give rise to new forms.

  4. Articulating Cross-Domain Resonances
    In this ontology, the same deep principles — system, relation, constraint, potential, actualisation — reverberate across physical, biological, and semiotic domains. Science becomes transdisciplinary, tracing echoes across levels of organisation.

  5. Reconceptualising Explanation
    Explanation moves from isolated cause to distributed coherence — from prediction by law to retrodiction through pattern. The goal is no longer to reduce complexity but to map its structuring principles.


A Science With and For Meaning

This reframing also shifts the ethos of science. No longer a detached observer standing outside the world, the scientist is a participant in the unfolding of relational potential. Inquiry is not a conquest of nature, but a dialogue with constraint — an effort to illuminate the resonances that shape what is possible, meaningful, and real.

This entails:

  • Acknowledging the semiotic dimension of science — that all theory, model, and measurement is a construal, a symbolic act within a meaning system.

  • Embracing reflexivity — recognising the knower as part of the known, the modeller as part of the system.

  • Valuing epistemic pluralism — not as relativism, but as a necessary response to the multidimensionality of pattern.

  • Seeking coherence across orders of reality — from matter to mind, system to symbol, physics to culture.


Beyond the Series: A Relational Vision for Inquiry

We close this series with an open horizon. Our aim has not been to displace science with philosophy, but to reorient science toward a more inclusive ontology — one that recognises the role of relation, constraint, and meaning in the very fabric of what we call “reality.”

In doing so, we offer:

  • A reinterpretation of scientific law, explanation, and causation as emergent from relation and system

  • A reconceptualisation of realism that honours both constraint and semiosis

  • A new foundation for scientific inquiry grounded in pattern, potential, and meaning

The implications, as we’ve already begun to explore, radiate outward — into thermodynamics, evolution, consciousness, culture. Each domain becomes a site not of mechanism but of resonance: a terrain where meaning condenses, unfolds, and is shaped by the attractors of system and constraint.

This is the promise of a relational ontology: not a retreat from science, but a deepening of its mission — to make visible the patterned potential of worlds within meaning.