1 Rethinking Fundamentality: The Standard Model in a Relational Ontology
In the standard account of particle physics, the so-called “fundamental particles” are the indivisible building blocks of nature, structured into families of fermions and bosons, all governed by quantum field theory and its unification under the Standard Model. But from the perspective of a relational ontology grounded in unfolding process, this picture invites a deep reconsideration.
Our ontology does not begin with things, but with fields of potential, instances of unfolding, and the relations that arise between them. In this model:
-
Particles are not fundamental objects.
-
They are coherent patterns—instantiated compressions of field potential.
-
Their stability and detectability are not signs of ontological primacy, but of highly individuated regularities across experimental conditions.
From Entities to Instantiated Constraints
In the conventional view, a particle like the electron is described as a point-like entity with fixed mass, charge, and spin. But what if instead, these attributes are not intrinsic properties but constraints on how certain regions of potential can unfold?
-
Mass is not a substance, but a measure of resistance to acceleration—an effect that emerges from how an instance constrains energy exchange across a relational field.
-
Charge is not a hidden feature of a thing, but a way of organising potential interactions under the rules of field symmetry and conservation.
-
Spin is not rotation, but a marker of how an instance transforms under symmetry operations.
All of these suggest that what we call “particles” are not irreducible bricks of matter, but stabilised instantiations of patterned relation, distinguished by how they persist, transform, and constrain within the semiotic system of physics.
Quantum Fields as Meaning Potentials
In the Standard Model, particles are excitations of quantum fields. This maps surprisingly well onto our own framing:
-
Fields are meaning potentials—structured spaces of possibility within which instantiations may occur.
-
Particles are not “in” the field but are instances of the field, actualised through relational constraint and interaction.
-
Measurement collapses this potential, not to a thing, but to a semiotically constrained value, interpreted through the social system of experimental physics.
Thus, the Standard Model becomes not a map of the ultimate furniture of reality, but a highly abstracted semiotic system, one that tracks the coherent instantiations of relations among physical fields in ways that are functionally predictive and materially constrained.
From Composition to Constraint
Crucially, in this ontology, one thing is not made of another. The ontology is not compositional but instantiational. A proton is not made of quarks, but rather:
-
The regular instantiation of the proton includes constraints that, when perturbed, manifest as patterns we name "quarks".
-
The rules governing these manifestations (like colour charge or confinement) are themselves metasemiotic constraints—rules not of substance but of allowable relation.
In this way, the relational ontology deflates the notion of 'fundamental' in favour of a more dynamic and process-oriented view of persistent regularities within interacting fields of potential.
2 Fields of Force: Coherence and Constraint in Relational Physics
In classical and quantum models alike, forces are described as interactions between entities—gravitational pulls, electromagnetic charges, nuclear attractions and repulsions. But what if this framing is a projection of substance metaphysics onto what are, more fundamentally, fields of relation?
In our relational ontology, we begin not with things that interact, but with fields of unfolding—potentials constrained into actualisation. Forces are not external exchanges between particles, but internal regularities within the unfolding of relation.
Force as Structured Constraint
Rather than treating force as a vector acting on a mass, we treat force as:
-
A patterned constraint on how a process unfolds.
-
A local compression in a larger relational topology.
-
A boundary condition that shapes the instantiation of energy, position, or momentum.
This turns familiar concepts on their head: gravitational “attraction” becomes a local unfolding along a shared geodesic; electromagnetic “repulsion” becomes a divergence of unfolding constrained by field symmetries.
Coherence Across Fields
From this perspective, what distinguishes one force from another is not the substance of the “interaction” but the type of coherence each field enforces:
-
Gravity: enforces coherence through shared unfolding toward mass centres—contracting spatial intervals and dilating temporal ones.
-
Electromagnetism: enforces coherence through polarity and field topology—governing how charged instances constrain one another across space.
-
Weak and Strong Nuclear Forces: operate not as 'forces between particles', but as deeply localised field constraints that regulate how certain types of unfolding (like decay or fusion) can be instantiated at all.
Each “force” is thus a grammar of unfolding—a set of conditions under which particular fields constrain and stabilise relation.
From Forces to Systems of Meaning
Physics construes these relational constraints using its own semiotic system—mathematics, diagrams, measurement. These systems don’t mirror reality; they instantiate meaning in disciplined ways that allow relational coherence to be tracked, predicted, and extended.
Force, then, is not a thing in the world—it is a construal of patterned relation: a semiotic scaffold that helps us navigate the energetic and spatial implications of co-unfolding fields.
Particles Revisited: Held by Fields
In this light, what holds particles together—inside an atom, a nucleus, or a proton—is not an internal composition of parts, but a co-instantiation of fields, made coherent by shared constraints:
-
The proton is not three quarks bound by gluons.
-
It is an instance of potential constrained by the topologies of colour confinement and nuclear coherence.
-
The fields do not sit beside the proton; they are the condition of its stability—the grammar through which it persists.
This view eliminates the idea that force is a separate entity, acting on things. Instead, it recasts forces as the inner logic of relational unfolding, organising what persists, what transforms, and what vanishes.
3 Symmetry, Meaning, and the Semiotics of the Standard Model
The Standard Model of particle physics is often celebrated as a triumph of modern science: a compact set of mathematical formulations that predicts with astonishing precision how particles behave and interact. But beneath this precision lies a deeper architecture—a semiotic system that construes the unfolding of reality through the lens of symmetry, quantisation, and constraint.
In our relational ontology, the Standard Model is not a theory about ultimate building blocks. It is a symbolic construal of fielded relations, organised through a specific grammar of mathematical meaning.
Symmetry as a Semiotic Principle
At the heart of the Standard Model lies symmetry. Group theory and gauge invariance are not simply mathematical tricks; they function as selection principles—ways of constraining how meaning is instantiated across physical processes.
Symmetries specify:
-
What can be transformed without changing the underlying structure (invariance).
-
Which kinds of unfolding are allowed or disallowed.
-
How relational potentials cohere into stable patterns.
In our terms, symmetry is a metafunctional scaffold: it constrains instantiation (what can happen) by organising potential across spatial, temporal, and energetic fields. These are not constraints on things, but on how processes can unfold and relate.
Quanta as Grammatical Units
Quantisation, too, is semiotic. It reflects not the discreteness of matter, but the discreteness of allowed relations under certain constraints.
Just as language has phonemes and morphemes—minimal units that cannot be subdivided meaningfully—quantum fields are described as having quanta, indivisible units of action, charge, or spin. These are not “particles” in the marble sense, but syntagmatic selections in a system of field potentials.
For example:
-
The electron is not a point-like object with fixed properties.
-
It is a constrained instantiation of a field with a particular set of symmetries (mass, charge, spin, lepton number).
-
What persists as the “electron” is a pattern of coherence within and across relational unfoldings.
In this sense, the Standard Model is not a map of stuff—it is a relational lexicogrammar, expressing how material systems can unfold, interact, and be instantiated.
The Standard Model as a Semiotic System
This reframing invites a radical reconstrual of what the Standard Model is:
-
It is not a description of the world as it is.
-
It is a semiotic system that instantiates a disciplined construal of potential, through quantised fields, symmetries, and interaction topologies.
Physics becomes one among many semiotic systems—but a particularly powerful one: one that has evolved to describe material regularities with a high degree of predictive power.
This doesn’t make it less “real.” On the contrary—it grounds its realism in how it constrains meaning across repeated instantiations. The Standard Model is not a mirror of nature but a grammar of what persists, what interacts, and what transforms under specific semiotic constraints.
From Model to Meaning
To understand the Standard Model relationally is to shift from a question of what the world is made of to how unfolding processes cohere under constraints that are expressible through symbolic systems. This brings the Standard Model into alignment with music, language, gesture, and other systems of meaning—not because it is subjective, but because it is structured, fielded, and selective.
Its great achievement is not that it reveals fundamental particles—but that it gives us a relational map of coherence within the broader topology of unfolding experience.
Coda: Reframing the Standard Model — From Substance to Semiotic Structure
As we step back from our relational re-examination of the Standard Model, a new picture comes into view. What was once presented as a catalogue of ultimate particles and forces now appears instead as a profound semiotic achievement: a symbolic system that constrains and organises how physical experience may be construed.
We began by reframing particles not as entities but as compressed patterns in fields of unfolding—points of coherence in relational processes. These patterns, sustained by symmetry constraints, emerge through structured interaction, not through intrinsic substance.
We then explored the forces and fields that govern these patterns, recognising them not as mediators between separate things but as the conditions for interaction within a topological system of relational unfolding. What physics names “forces” become modalities of coherence, maintaining the persistence or transformation of structured relations.
And in this final post, we’ve seen that symmetry and quantisation function not only mathematically but semiotically, as a kind of lexicogrammar: a structured meaning potential governing how the universe is construed within physics. The Standard Model is not a window into substance—it is a semiotic interface between conscious observers and the patterned potentials of our world.
In this view, the “reality” described by physics is perspectival. It is not what is there before or beneath experience, but what emerges when consciousness construes fielded potentials through symbolic systems. The Standard Model is one such system—highly evolved, extraordinarily precise, but still an organised construal of meaning, not an ontological finality.
By moving beyond the marble metaphor—beyond particles as things—and embracing the ontology of relational unfolding, we open space for new connections: between physics and music, between symmetry and signification, between biological value and cultural form. We come to see that meaning is not a late addition to a material world. It is the very mode through which reality is construed, instantiated, and known.
The Standard Model, in this light, becomes not an answer to what the world is made of, but a powerful expression of how coherence is sustained in the dance of unfolding potential—a relational grammar of the real.